Circuits of Colonial Knowledge

For the October 2019 issue of History of the Human Sciences, the editors are delighted to present a special issue edited by Bruce Buchan (Griffith University) and Linda Andersson Burnett (Linnaeus University) – “Knowing Savagery: Humanity in the Circuits of Colonial Knowledge.” Here, Chris Renwick speaks to to Bruce and Linda about what the stakes of the issue – and draws out some of its central contributions.

Chris Renwick (CR): “Knowing Savagery” is a brilliant special issue for History of the Human Sciences. It brings together a wide range of topics that have a bearing on questions about how our understanding of the human has been shaped. I wondered whether there was a particular spur for the special issue on the topic and you see as the main points you think a HHS audience will take away from it? 

Bruce Buchan and Linda Andersson Burnett (BB & LAB): Our special issue is the product of a long collaboration. We are both intellectual historians whose work explores the connections between European traditions of thought and the experience of colonisation, both within Europe and beyond. Though we have different fields of specialisation (Linda on the history of travel, natural history and Nordic colonialism, and Bruce on political ideas with a focus on Australia’s colonial history) what we share is an interest in uncovering the colonial burden wrapped up in concepts, and the words we use to convey them. Thanks to the generosity of the Riksbankens Jubileumsfond in Sweden, we’ve been able to pursue this idea through a joint research project entitled ‘The Borders of Humanity: Linnaean Natural Historians and the Colonial Legacies of Enlightenment’. Our special issue forms part of this project and gives a more formal shape to what we’ve learned by working collaboratively with so many wonderful scholars. 

Linda Andersson Burnett

We hope that readers of History of the Human Sciences will take away from our special issue a greater appreciation for the sometimes unpredictable ways in which European concepts facilitated colonisation globally. We also hope that readers will see how the very processes of colonisation around the world shaped the development of European thought on humanity. Our aim was not to attempt a comprehensive global coverage, but a series of targeted case studies examining various dimensions of this conceptual change in relation to one main concept: savagery.

CR: The articles in the special issue are indeed focused on the topic of “savagery”. One of the main conclusions I took away from them – your own article in particular – was that, as a non-specialist, I’d probably assumed much more continuity between “savagery” and “race” than there actually was between the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. That seems a particularly significant point, with quite far reaching historiographic implications. Are there issues or questions that you think are the next step in taking these conclusions forwards? 

BB & LAB: Savagery was an old concept long before the period covered by most of the papers in our special issue, namely the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Antonella Romano’s paper in particular demonstrates this by considering how Iberian missionaries began to refer to savagery in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.  Yet for all its antiquity the term ‘savagery’ has often been misunderstood. It is frequently confined to eighteenth century debates over supposedly ‘noble’ versus ‘ignoble’ savages. What we wanted to accomplish with this special issue was to branch out beyond such debates and to consider savagery in a wider set of contexts: by means of intellectual, emotional, religious, sensory, cross-cultural histories and the history of science. We hoped that by doing so, we could show how savagery became so deeply embedded in the ways that Europeans interpreted and evaluated other peoples, that it also shaped how Europeans understood themselves. 

In part, this is an exercise in excavating savagery from the layers of European thought in the era of Enlightenment. Silvia Sebastiani’s paper accomplishes this by examining the history of anatomy. Hanna Hodacs and Matthias Persson’s joint paper explores savagery in relation to political economy and evangelism. Jacqueline Van Gent’s paper considers savagery in missionary discourses. Having excavated savagery however, we were intent on showing the role it played in conceptual change and development, as Sarah Irving-Stonebreaker and Gunlög Fur do in their papers.

Bruce Buchan

In our own paper we wanted to explore the way in which savagery was integrated into the way in which ‘Enligthened’ natural historians and colonial travellers understood the very concept of ‘humanity’. Here is where we see the need for more research, following the lead of scholars such as Emmanuel Eze, Roxann Wheeler, Silvia Sebastiani and others who have drawn our attention to the intimate connections between race, humanity and Enlightenment. What we argue in our paper is that Enlightenment ascriptions of a universal humanity were gradated by ascriptions of savagery, but also by terms such as race and variety. These were still ambiguous terms in the late eighteenth century, but they were coming to be defined by a growing focus on alleged anatomical differences between human populations, suggesting a more static or fixed set of attributes to each variety or race. What is particularly interesting for us is that those attributes included not only physical characteristics (such as skin colour), but what might be termed moral or social qualities as well (such as language, religion or forms of government). It was these latter qualities that the term ‘savagery’ had previously been used to delineate, but in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries a discursive change took place that was to have dramatic consequences in the centuries to follow. This was not a clear transition from a discourse of savagery to one centred on race. The change was messy but its effect were that race subsumed rather than replaced savagery. We feel very strongly that the time is right for further research on this discursive change – both on the historical moment and its antecedents, and on the important consequences, the effects of which still linger. Not only are we witnessing a distressing resurgence of spurious claims about the ‘science’ of racial differences, the troubling legacies of Europe’s Enlightenment are also being debated with renewed vigour around the world. At the forefront of these legacies are the long-term consequences of our inherited language of race and savagery.

CR: Your special issue engages with a range of different approaches to savagery, as we’d probably expect, given its interest in the circulation of knowledge.  Over all, though, you seem most concerned with the intellectual dimensions of savagery. Was there a reason for that? Especially as historians of science have been more enamoured with material and ethnographic dimensions of such problems in the recent past.    

BB & LAB: That’s right, but we wanted to add a different dimension to this important research by paying greater attention to the language used by natural historians, missionaries, and colonists who travelled around the world, as well as the intellectuals who taught them and often never left Europe. The guiding principle of our collaboration is that the terms we use to convey thought have complicated histories, and that recovering those histories requires an acknowledgement that language is not innocent. Savagery was a term of great use in the task of state formation in Europe, and was just as useful in the process of imperial expansion. It conveyed a knowledge about human groups and their amenability to colonisation, and so we wanted our special issue to focus on how the term, and the knowledge it implied, circulated within and between imperial and colonial domains. That circulation involved some unpredictable confrontations and reversals of meaning (notably when Indigenous people rebuked Europeans as savages, or missionaries expressed horror at the savagery of colonial violence). But even here, in tracing the intellectual history of savagery the material element is crucial. Savagery subsisted in the pages of the journals that natural historians wrote, it lived within the pages of the books they read and carried with them on their journeys, and it was inscribed on the artefacts that they collected and sent back to Europe, which was in effect a physical curation of humanity.

CR: Your special issue deals with savagery in the context of empires, rather than any single empire. One of the great things about the issue you’ve put together is that it involves bringing together a number of different histories that make it a global history of its topic, which in the process brings things to the attention of an English-reading audience work that they might not be familiar with. This is the kind of thing HHS likes to encourage. Could say a little more about the challenges and opportunities that editors face in doing it? 

BB & LAB: One of the problems that scholars in the English-speaking world face is the predominance of an Anglo-centric perspective. This predominance takes many forms, but one of its effects has been a tendency to consider the history of colonisation through the lens of the British Empire. The presumption is quaint of course. Scholars of the Iberian empires (such as Antonella Romano in our special issue) can point to global influences at least as extensive as that of Britain’s. The point though is not about the extent or duration of imperial influence, but the degree to which we fall under the spell of ’empire’ itself. Scholars can tend to speak of various empires (British, Spanish, Dutch, etc) as if they were monolithic entities that acted rather like international relations scholars sometimes think states act today: moved by a centre of power, devoted to the pursuit of particular interests, and so on. 

As we see it, intellectual history offers us a way to complicate these presumptions about empire by showing how profoundly the language of colonisation flowed across imperial and colonial frontiers, and was of course decisively shaped by confrontations and engagements with non-European and Indigenous peoples across the globe. By working with the team of scholars represented in this special issue of History of the Human Sciences we’ve been able to highlight at least some of these dimensions of complication: where for example Swedish missionaries were confronted by Lenape interlocutors in colonial North America; or how knowledge of the orangutan circulated through and across Dutch and British empires, brokered by a range of intellectuals and intermediaries spanning the globe; or why the confusion of both French and British colonial natural historians about how to describe (and to picture) Indigenous Australians illustrated the ambiguities of race and savagery.

This is the opportunity that working with a trans-national team of researchers makes possible, but it is matched by challenges of translation and interpretation. In part this is a question of how to make wonderful scholarship in one language available in another. The broader point however, is one of integrating knowledge and making it comprehensible. Our collaborators combine diverse expertise in histories of cross-cultural encounter, histories of science or the emotions, histories of trade and travel, or the history of ideas and concepts across a broad sweep of time from the Renaissance to the mid-nineteenth century. It is here that our thematic focus on savagery provides an avenue for meaningful communication across these divides. In the process we open up more possibilities to challenge the continuing presumption of scholarship that remains both Anglo-centric and bound to empire. 

Bruce Buchan is an intellectual historian at Griffith University, whose work traces the entanglement of European political thought with the experience of empire and colonisation, focussing on the Early Modern and Enlightenment periods.

Linda Andersson Burnett is a historian of the Enlightenment and Linnaean natural history at Linnaeus University, with a research focus on the exchange of scientific, economic and cultural thought between British and Scandinavian intellectuals in the Enlightenment period, and the importance of colonial and nation-building encounters with marginalised and indigenous social groups in the development of these thought exchanges.

Chris Renwick is senior lecturer in modern history at the University of York and an editor of HHS.

History of the Human Sciences Early Career Prize

History of the Human Sciences – the international journal of peer-reviewed research, which provides the leading forum for work in the social sciences, humanities, human psychology and biology that reflexively examines its own historical origins and interdisciplinary influences – is delighted to announce its new annual prize for early career scholars. The intention of the award is to recognise a researcher whose work best represents the journal’s aim to critically examine traditional assumptions and preoccupations about human beings, their societies and their histories in light of developments that cut across disciplinary boundaries. In the pursuit of these goals, History of the Human Sciences publishes traditional humanistic studies as well work in the social sciences, including the fields of sociology, psychology, political science, the history and philosophy of science, anthropology, classical studies, and literary theory. Scholars working in any of these fields are encouraged to apply.

Guidelines for the Award

Scholars who wish to be considered for the award are asked to submit an up-to-date CV (a maximum of two pages in length and including a statement that confirms eligibility for the award) and an essay that is a maximum of 12,000 words long (including footnotes and references). The essay should be unpublished and not under consideration elsewhere, based on original research, written in English, and follow History of the Human Science’s style guide. Scholars are advised to read the journal’s description of its aims and scope, as well as its submission guidelines.

Essays will be judged by a panel drawn from the journal’s editorial team and board. They will identify the essay from the field of entries that best fits the journal’s aims and scope.

Eligibility

Scholars of any nationality who have either not yet been awarded a PhD or are no more than five years from its award are welcome to apply. The judging panel will use the definition of “active years”, with time away from academia for parental leave, health problems, or other relevant reasons not counting towards the definition of eligibility.

Prize

The winning scholar will be awarded £250 and have their essay published in History of the Human Sciences (subject to the essay passing through the journal’s peer review process). The intention is to award the prize to a single entrant but the judging panel may choose to recognise more than one essay in the event of a particularly strong field.

Deadlines

Entries should be made by 31st January 2020. The panel will aim to make a decision by 1st May 2020. The winning entry will be submitted for peer review automatically. The article, clearly identified as the winner of the History of the Human Sciences Early Career Prize, will then be published in the journal as soon as the production schedule allows. The winning scholar and article will also be promoted by History of the Human Sciences, including on its website, which hosts content separate to the journal.

To Apply

Entrants should e-mail an anonymised copy of their essay, along with an up-to-date CV, to hhs@histhum.com

Further Enquiries

If you have any questions about the prize, or anything relating to the journal, please email hhs@histhum.com

Thinking Differently in the USSR

Rebecca Reich. State of Madness: Psychiatry, Literature and Dissent After Stalin; DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, 2018; 280 pages; hardback £45.00; ISBN: 0875807755

By Hannah Proctor

Rebecca Reich’s State of Madness focuses on discourses surrounding punitive psychiatry in the Soviet Union in the years between Stalin’s death in 1953 and the collapse of the Soviet Union in 1991. Much of the existing literature on the pathologisation of dissent, stories of which began to emerge and spread via samizdat in the 1960s, has an institutional emphasis, whereas Reich focuses on relationships between literature and psychiatry. In the context of a state system of psychiatry that understood dissent as a form of insanity and attributed ‘political resistance to a distinctive state of mind’ (p. 62), resistance was imagined by those resisting as a sane response to a mad system. Dissidents–a broad term that does not necessarily imply engagement in political activism–worked to ‘validate a norm of inakomyslie, or “thinking differently”’ by challenging the state’s authority to diagnose insanity (p. 217). Reich demonstrates that literature was a key site for contesting psychiatric diagnoses, becoming a ‘source of diagnostic authority’ in its own right (p. 6). State of Madness is always working with and through contested dichotomies; there is neither dissent nor madness without a norm. Sanity then becomes a question of who is responsible for defining and assigning the diagnostic categories.

State of Madness examines literature from a range of genres produced during the period after Stalin’s death that challenged the theoretical frameworks and practices of psychiatry. In the case studies considered by Reich the boundaries between the aesthetic and the psychiatric  – along with those between sanity and insanity – are often blurred. Reich does far more than merely analyse aesthetic representations of psychiatry, however. Not only does she discuss how psychiatrists themselves deployed aesthetic conventions in their clinical documents, but her analysis of the interplay between literature and psychiatry is grounded in an understanding of life in the Soviet Union as thoroughly aestheticised: ‘the state went about constructing socialism by applying its creative principles to reality itself’ (p. 50). The question of identifying distinctions between art and life was an urgent one for some of the figures she discusses precisely because it was so hard to discern.

In her introduction, Reich traces the ‘deceptive similarities’ between Soviet dissident narratives and the works of Michel Foucault, noting that although his discussions of the normative impulses of psychiatry echoed Soviet concerns, his analyses pertained to liberal societies and thus cannot fully account for the authoritarianism of the Soviet Union. (Though it could be noted that this does not mean dissent has not been pathologised in the kinds of societies Foucault was analysing, as Jonathan Metzl’s The Protest Psychosis: How Schizophrenia Became a Black Disease demonstrates with regard to Ionia State Hospital in Michigan in the 1960s.) In addition to identifying such theoretical convergences and divergences, Reich later situates Soviet abuses of psychiatry in relation to contemporaneous Western critiques of psychiatry, often bracketed together under the baggy and contested term ‘antipsychiatry’. News of the pathologisation of Soviet dissidents emerged in the West at the very moment these ideas were at their most popular, and chimed with the notion that psychiatric institutions and nosologies were inherently oppressive. More interestingly, Reich also discusses how the repudiation of antipsychiatry in mainstream Soviet psychiatry journals ironically led to those ideas circulating in the Soviet Union. She discusses examples of people who acquainted themselves with this material and found that it spoke to the Soviet experience: ‘trickling down through sanctioned and unsanctioned channels, Western antipsychiatric ideas informed the critical vocabulary through which Soviet dissidents exposed abuse’ (p. 65).

Rebecca Reich

Reich begins by discussing the literary discourses Soviet psychiatrists themselves engaged with, underlining that the psychiatric norms dissidents were reacting against were expressed in terms that were congruent with Soviet literary conventions. She thus establishes from the very beginning that the lines of influence between psychiatry and aesthetics flowed in both directions. By applying a formal literary analysis to clinical documents, Reich convincingly demonstrates that the discipline of psychiatry was structured according to an ‘established aesthetic framework’ borrowing from the ‘literary doctrine of Socialist Realism’ (p. 27, p. 29). Psychiatrists framed their diagnostic practices as a kind of artistic endeavour and pathologised aesthetic modes that deviated from the standards of Socialist Realism.

According to Reich, diagnostic categories furnished psychiatrists with ‘predictive templates for narrating’ the lives of dissidents (p. 43). The psychiatrist drew out the ‘essence’ of a patient’s life story through a spoken discussion and effectively muffled the patient’s own account in the process, which Reich frames, drawing on the work of Soviet literary scholar Bakhtin, as a shift from dialogue to monologue (p. 44). A further stage of mediation then occurred when the ‘essence’ extracted verbally was converted into writing in the form of a clinical report in which the subjective interpretations of the psychiatrist, along with the aestheticising qualities of diagnosis, tended to be obscured by the neutral tone of medical objectivity. Yet Reich argues that in spite of their authors’ impartial intentions, forensic reports nonetheless amplified the always partial voices of Soviet psychiatrists, whom Reich argues narrated their patients’ conditions in a manner that conformed to the teleology of the Socialist Realist ‘master plot’, situating syndromes and processes of recovery in a progressive narrative.

Psychiatrists also turned their diagnostic gaze on the artistic and literary outputs of their dissident patients. In line with state-sanctioned understandings of art, figurative work was associated with sanity and aesthetic harmony was associated with mental healing. Normative aesthetic judgments and literary categories were transferred from artworks to individual psyches which, Reich argues, betrayed a failure to understand the sophisticated artistic movements of the period – such as Moscow Conceptualism or Sots-Arts – that relied heavily on irony, kitsch and parody, and self-consciously critiqued Socialist Realist tropes.

But literature was – conversely – a site for contesting psychiatry’s art of diagnosis, which Reich moves on to discuss in the book’s second chapter and in three subsequent case studies. The ambiguities of psychiatric discourse and diagnostic categories facilitated their punitive use, but writers also played with these ambiguities for their own ends: ‘their psychiatric narratives reveal a shared perception that psychiatric abuse had resulted both from the ambiguity psychiatric discourse itself and from the state’s conflation of inakomyslie, or ‘thinking differently’, with insanity’ (p. 60). The monologism Reich identifies as characteristic of Soviet psychiatry in the first chapter is replaced in the second by the dialogue introduced by dissidents ‘that embraced singularity, irony, and open-endedness’ (p. 93). If psychiatrists had absorbed the conventions of Soviet Socialist Realism as part of their pathologisation of dissidents in these counter examples, by contrast, ‘literary discourse assimilates psychiatric discourse to depathologize inakonmyslie and to pathologize both society and the state’ (p. 96).

The book’s first ‘case’ focuses on Joseph Brodsky with an argument animated by his reversal of Marx’s dictum ‘existence conditions consciousness’. Here dialogism becomes literalised through a discussion of his narrative poem ‘Gorbunov and Gorchakov’, set in a psychiatric hospital, which takes the form of a discussion between two characters embodying different concepts. Brodsky is not deemed to have been hospitalised for punitive reasons and, unlike the dissidents discussed in the previous chapter, was not a political activist. But the significance of his diagnosis and institutionalisation for Reich is ‘the sense it appears to have given the poet that the primary purpose of the psychiatric profession was to enforce a linguistic regime of existence’ (p. 108).

Andrei Siniavskii (along with his pseudonymous alter ego Abram Terts) is the second of Reich’s three case studies. In 1965 he was arrested and found imputable by psychiatrists who examined his literary output for evidence of pathology, thus enacting the very melding of life and art that his previous works critiqued. Siniavskii developed an understanding of the aesthetic process at odds with that espoused by the state, which propounded a vision of creativity in line with Lenin’s ‘reflection theory’ [teoriia otrazheniia]. This extended the dictum of Marx, that Brodsky drew upon, by claiming that consciousness and existence – or humanity and nature – existed in a mutually transformative relationship with one another; people were shaped by their circumstances but could also intervene in the world to transform it. This, Reich explains, had a counterpart in psychiatry in the form of reflex theory [reflekornaia teoriia]. According to Reich, mirrors and other reflective surfaces litter Terts’s works, figuring as surfaces that distort the reality they claim to show: ‘It was by concealing rather than revealing reality’s essence… that the state had driven society mad.’ (p. 184). His works imagined art, alternatively, as the site where it might be possible to promote a deeper awareness of reality by highlighting its strangeness and artifice, departing from Lenin and drawing instead on Viktor Shklovskii’s notion of ‘defamiliarization’ [ostranenie] as an ‘antidote to creative madness’ (p. 153). For Siniavskii/Terts, who developed a form of Fantastic Realism as a counterpart to the officially sanctioned conventions of Socialist Realism, the antidote to reflection in art was not achieved through a greater fidelity to reality but, paradoxically, through estrangement from it.

Reich’s concluding ‘case’ focuses on Venedikt Erofeev, a writer whose chaotic and often inebriated life paralleled the social deviance of his literary heroes, who also bore his name. Here the smudged line between life and art and Erofeev’s self-conscious attempts to play with this blurriness, returns in the guise of a tussle between madness and its simulation. The theatrical feigning of mental illness as a means of avoiding imprisonment was a practice Soviet psychiatrists were aware of, and Reich situates Erofeev’s work in this context arguing that it ‘captures the risks of simulating madness in an irrational world of ever more meaningless diagnostic categories’ (p. 188).

Alcohol was Erofeev’s primary material in his performative experiments which danced along the border between sanity and insanity, a pair of categories that had a counterpart in the relationship between simulation and dissimulation: at what point does the performance become a reality? Or does simulating madness as it is defined by a ‘mad’ state paradoxically stave off real madness? Erofeev eventually lost control of his own experiment and sought out treatment as the alcohol induced hallucinations and delirium that had characterised his writing became a part of his lived experience. The staged pathologisation soon became inseparable from life.

As in other chapters of State of Madness, in Erofeev’s work distinctions are constantly breaking down: between sanity and insanity, simulation and dissimulation, the theatrical and the real, the asylum and society, and, ultimately, between literature and real life. The mask of madness gradually became indistinguishable from the face beneath. Yet if, as Reich argues, Erofeev’s play Walpurgis Night exposes ‘the fact that it is society that has lost its mind’ (p. 203), the question remains whether sanity can ever really exist or even be defined within a crazy world: ‘how were they to calibrate their health in a society where, as they so frequently portrayed it, madness was the psychological norm?’ (p. 15) Ultimately for Erofeev, ‘the only certainty is the theatricality with which both categories [sanity and insanity] manifest themselves’ (p. 205). Reich describes dissidents stuck in a ‘discursive trap’ and the examples she considers describe these traps from within or sometimes construct new ones but they struggle to find ways of escaping altogether (p. 61). It’s enough to drive anyone mad.

If dissent is the norm then what happens when society changes? I would have been intrigued to read an epilogue considering what became of these discourses after the Soviet Union – and its attendant master plots and meta-narratives – collapsed. Of the three writers Reich discusses in most detail, Brodky and Siniavskii both lived past 1991. Brodsky left the Soviet Union in 1972 but the implication is that this geographical displacement did not lead to a sudden sanity and he instead experienced ‘the maddening freedom of exile’ (p. 20). The Soviet ‘state of madness’ may have had particular contours but this suggests that there may be no such thing as a ‘state of sanity’. The dissident writers Reich discusses ‘assumed the role of psychiatrists to an authoritarian state that had lost its mind’ (p. 19), but the lingering anxiety remains that identifying this madness could provide neither an individual nor societal cure. Reich’s book attests that literature nonetheless remained a privileged site for contending with the impasse. As Brodsky wrote in ‘A Part of Speech’ (1975-76):

It may be the heel that’s slipping on ice, or it may be the earth

that’s turning beneath the heel. (p. 137)

Hannah Proctor is Wellcome Trust Research Fellow at the Centre for the Social History of Health and Healthcare at the University of Strathclyde.

Some semblance of a ‘field’

In February this year, HHS published a special issue on ‘the future of the history of the human sciences, edited by Chris Renwick. That issue (and the event it drew from) brought together scholars from a wide range of backgrounds and institutional positions, to reflect on the constitution of ‘the history of the human sciences’ as a field – and also to think through its possible or likely futures. Representing, perhaps, different ‘generational’ approaches to these concerns were Roger Smith (now working independently in the Russian Federation, and a Reader Emeritus in History of Science at Lancaster University), who wrote on resistance to the neurosciences, and Alexandra Bacopoulos-Viau (a Vising Fellow at Weill Cornell Psychiatry, and associate member of the Department of History and Classical Studies at McGill) who wrote on the discovery of the unconscious. Here, Alexandra puts some questions to Roger on the past and present of the history of the human sciences as a field.

Alexandra Bacopoulos-Viau (ABV): Roger, how has the history of the human science – as a field – changed since you were a graduate student?

Roger Smith (RS): There was no field of history of the human sciences when I was a graduate student (1967-70). Very little activity in the history of science concerned the non-physical sciences; and the separate social science and psychological disciplines wrote narrow histories for internal consumption. The phrase ‘the human sciences’ was uncommon (though in France, sciences humaines and les sciences de l’homme were well-established terms, each with its own connotation in intellectual life). The change, to which I contributed, was the constitution of some semblance of a ‘field’ of history of the human sciences in the second half of the 1980s, and the piecemeal spread thereafter of reference to the term. Then and now, the identity of the field, its novelty and its trajectory are issues open to debate. It was precisely the value of an umbrella term under which to debate questions roused across existing disciplinary borders that encouraged the use of the term, practices to go with it, and the founding of the eponymous journal in the first place. The way the field has developed has varied considerably in response to local institutional pressures and purposes.

Reference to the existence of the field is now much more common, though hardly general. I am not aware, however, that the identity of the field has substantially changed (however much specific content may be local). In addressing this, though, and in relation to your other questions too, readers will want to bear in mind that I have worked outside a UK institutional setting for over twenty years. I hope other answers will qualify what I say. I note, almost randomly, a few points. Many people feel that the neuro-disciplines demand new recognition, accommodation or critique, and the history of the human sciences has responded to that. Attention to Michel Foucault’s work has been remarkably sustained, relating both to his writings and to the critical lever given by pursuing ‘the history of the present’, leading to analysis of ‘regimes of truth’ in the social and psychological sciences. There has been a spate of good work on post-World War 2 human sciences, mediating between historical knowledge and current concerns. Explicit political critique is less common and there are more signs of conformity to professional standards – though it cannot be said that history of the human sciences has any standards peculiar to itself as a field. The standard of basic contextual reference in historical writing now seems well established. I would much like to know if other people think there have indeed been, or are about to be, changes.

ABV: What do you think are the biggest challenges facing the field today?

RS: Intellectually, the challenges are as they were: to provide leadership in situating ‘the human’, or the knowledge-constituting process, at the centre of the sciences. This continuously and necessarily demands open-ended debate about the ontology of these processes and engagement with notions of ‘the human’. The issues are so complex and have been discussed with such intense abstraction in so many specialised ways, that there is huge scope for collective projects and forums rendering the issues more concrete in specific historical settings. I think it is up to the history of the human science to show the work it does is central to the rhetoric (in the deep, constructive, collective sense) of taking the issues further. Work in the field provides models of ‘the golden mean’ between high theory and historical empiricism. The history of the human sciences needs to do more to bring in the intellectual riches of fields such as comparative ethnology and linguistics. I also increasingly value studies which are well written and manifestly wish to communicate (which has nothing to so with ‘dumbing down’).

I also think it’s a challenge for scholars who work in the field to restate what they think are the relations between ‘the human sciences’ and ‘the history of the human sciences’. I often do not know in what sense contributors think (if they do so think) that they work in a field under the title of ‘history’. I would welcome more studies with a long time perspective on ‘the human’. Some think that there is a contemporary ‘transformation’ of the human, and of course to describe such a transformation requires some reference to a ‘before’ as well as to an ‘after’. Certainly, disciplined history of the human sciences ought in this context to be a major resource.

And institutionally, the challenges are the challenges facing the humanities in general, and it is hardly news to say that these are large and disturbing. the history of the human sciences ought to be at the forefront of the rational demonstration that the pursuit of knowledge cannot be built on measures of production taken from the business world. But of course the argument is with political processes which reject the value or pertinence of rationally formulated knowledge.  

ABV: What do you make of the promises / limits of interdisciplinarity?

RS: Interdisciplinarity (however understood) has been around for decades, if not a century or more. The history of the human sciences was constituted as an interdisciplinary field; the history of this field should therefore provide a kind of empirical commentary on the promises and limits of interdisciplinarity itself. The field houses an excellent body of practice and exemplary range of discussions to offer to those seeking to move out of narrowly disciplinary-focused studies. I think the constitution of a domain shaped by long-term assumptions about the relevance of a great range of disciplines and topics (from art history to studies of utopias) to shared problems, has a lot going for it. Publishers don’t seem to share this view, unfortunately, and work according to preconceived market slots (which of course include the slots that goes with famous names). By and large, there is no need to keep talking about interdisciplinarity while the option of doing the history of the human sciences is on the table.

ABV: What excites you most about the future?

RS: I guess this is a question about the field – the future ‘in general’, given the strident failures of political processes, is, shall we say, hard to get excited about. (Utopian ideas may be another matter.) I get excited about particular projects, rather than about ‘a field’, especially one as nebulous as the history of the human sciences. So you will have to excuse me if I call to mind my current project, a book on The Sense of Movement: An Intellectual History (in press). It would be exciting if I could, by this means, reassert the value of intellectual history, link history of science and the history of the human sciences, write the history of a sense and explain what is ‘moving’ about feeling movement (it requires wide-ranging answers). It’s exciting that there is a lot of good work being done, for example, on the history of the emotions, on the culture of the senses, on the constitution of categories like ‘depression’, and on recognition of the data of comparative ethnography about representations of ‘the human’. A lot of people, happily, see that the umbrella category, ‘the history of the human sciences’, has the intellectual and social potential to hold in constructive relation particular studies of the large issues at stake.

Alexandra Bacopoulos-Viau is a Vising Fellow at Weill Cornell Psychiatry, and associate member of the Department of History and Classical Studies at McGill University. With Aude Fauvel, she is the editor of “Tales from the Asylum. Patient Narratives and the (De)construction of Psychiatry,” a special issue of Medical History.

Roger Smith is an an independent scholar in the Russian Federation and a Reader Emeritus in the History of Science at Lancaster University. Among many contributions, he is the author of Being Human: Historical Knowledge and the Creation of Human Nature.

Understanding Others

Susan Lanzoni. Empathy: A History; New Haven and London: Yale University Press; 408 pages; hardback $30.00; ISBN: 9780300222685

by Sarah Chaney

A couple of years ago, I attended a colloquium on empathy at the University of Oxford. The organisers of this event were rightly concerned by the vague and varied definitions of empathy in medical research and practice and sought to remedy this. While they had found a number of clinical trials that purported to measure empathy, the introductory lecture noted, every single one of these gave a slightly different definition of what it was they were actually measuring! As Susan Lanzoni’s comprehensive history of empathy shows, this conceptual confusion around empathy is not new. Even after an explosion of interest in the term through the 1950s and 1960s, in 1979 the American social psychologist Kenneth B. Clark declared himself dismayed by the lack of “clear definition and a comprehensive theoretical approach” to the subject (p. 248).

As Lanzoni shows in this genealogy, the confusion lies to some extent in the fact that the meaning of the term has “shifted so radically that its original meaning transformed into its opposite” (p. 8). Lanzoni makes this shift clear by outlining a huge range of examples of studies in which empathy does not mean what the modern reader might expect. To take just one example of many, when the psychologist Edward Bullough found in 1908 that his subjects described coloured lights as having a particular temperament or character he called this “empathy” (p. 52). Even in the twenty-first century, many forms of empathy exist: “from emotional resonance and contagion, to cognitive appraisal and perspective taking, and to an empathic concern with another that prompts helpful intervention” (p. 252). While the book takes a chronological approach to the subject, the diversity of different meanings at play in any one period are thus made clear throughout.

Lanzoni records the first use of the term “empathy” simultaneously in English in 1908 by the psychologists James Ward and Edward Titchener, used in both cases as a translation of the German Einfühlung. Jeffrey Aronson has dated this a little earlier, finding the English word empathy in The Philosophical Review of 1895. Quibbles about the exact date aside, however, Lanzoni rightly emphasises the importance of the origins of empathy in the aesthetic Einfühlung (empathy was later translated back into German psychology as “empathie”). Empathy thus emerged from the appreciation of art and was first conceptualised as an ability to project oneself into an artwork or object; early psychological definitions also incorporated this notion of empathy as an extension or projection of the self. By the post-war period, however, empathy increasingly became viewed as a way of understanding others, a notion that was particularly prominent in the field of social work. It was this latter idea of empathy that was popularised after the Second World War.

Of course, the distinction is not so clear or neat in practice. Indeed, Lanzoni cites the German psychologist and philosopher Theodor Lipps as having suggested that Einfühlung was a way to understand the emotions of others as early as 1903, while modern neuroscientific definitions often hark back to aesthetic empathy through the links made to visual images and movement (p. 265). For ease of narrative, however, Lanzoni divides the history of empathy into nine historical stages. She begins with empathy in the arts as a way of “feeling into objects” and closes with mirror neurons as an expression of empathy in the modern neurosciences. On the way, the book takes in the experimental laboratory, art and modern dance, the psychiatric hospital, social work, psychometrics, popular depictions of empathy and the politics of social psychology. While the early chapters, on the introduction of the word, include aesthetic and psychological research across Europe, the second half of the book tends to focus more closely on the United States. This is perhaps the opposite of what one might anticipate, as the post-war era moved towards a supposedly international culture. Further explanation of the reasons for the chosen focus would thus have been helpful to the reader, or the occasional reflection on how the North American field complemented or differed from research elsewhere.

The chapters vary in their presentation: some chart changes over a period in a particular area such as social work, others focus in more detail on a specific person or theory. A good example of the former approach is chapter six, on the post-war measuring of empathy, a comprehensive account of North American efforts to test for empathy in the wake of Rosalind Dymond’s student test at Cornell University in 1948. These tests are highlighted by Lanzoni as they marked a shift in understanding of empathy from a creative enterprise to an “accurate understanding of another’s thoughts” (p. 176). In contrast, chapter 8 on the 1960s relationship between social psychology, race and politics, focuses largely on the social psychologist Kenneth B. Clark. This seems to be a particular interest of Lanzoni’s (she has also written about Clark for the Washington Post) and she sensitively weaves Clark’s concerns about the centrality of capitalist greed in White American society, and prejudice as a social disease, into his psychological research on the topic of empathy. This culminated in the publication of Clark’s Dark Ghetto in 1965, an ethology of Harlem explicitly aiming to “inform, to engender feeling, and to galvanize social action” (p. 240).

At times, the sheer amount of content means that Lanzoni veers into a rather descriptive style. Some chapters are heavy on chronological lists of contributions with less focus on how these fit into a broader picture. Chapter 3, on empathy in art and modern dance, for example, might have been edited down and combined with the previous chapter to indicate the links between experimental psychology and aesthetics in a more directed way. And while the material on Clark is undoubtedly interesting, a greater degree of contextualisation into the contemporary civil rights movement (which is merely nodded at in passing) would have been useful. There are also some significant absences. For instance, while occasional debates around the distinction between empathy, sympathy and compassion briefly surface (such as Edward Titchener’s claim that sympathy referred to fellow feeling, whereas empathy reflected an imagined but unfamiliar feeling [p. 66] ), the reader is left wondering why more attention was not paid to the interplay and conflict between these ideas.

Overall, however, Lanzoni’s book ably charts the complex changes in meaning that empathy has undergone over the last century, and convincingly argues that much of this confusion remains today. This is important, given how often empathy is invoked in a wide range of arenas in the modern world – from politics to education to health and medicine. As Lanzoni recognises, empathy is frequently emphasised as a vital human capacity, something that has the power to shape society for the better. Does it matter that we remain unable to convincingly explain what exactly it is or how it functions? Perhaps not, Lanzoni concludes, so long as we are aware of this complexity. Across all its definitions, empathy is characterised as a “technology of self”. This means that understanding its complex history can serve to increase our ability to make connections.

Sarah Chaney is a Research Fellow at Queen Mary Centre for the History of the Emotions, on the Wellcome Trust funded ‘Living With Feeling’ project. Her current research focuses on the history of compassion in healthcare, from the late nineteenth century to the present day, and includes an exhibition to open at the Royal College of Nursing Library and Heritage Centre in December 2019. Her previous research has been in the history of psychiatry, in particular the topic of self-inflicted injury. Her monograph, Psyche on the Skin: A History of Self-Harmis published in paperback in July 2019 (first published 2017).

Time with a capital T

In the April 2019 issue of History of the Human Sciences, Allegra Fryxell, from the Faculty of History at the University of Cambridge, published ‘Psychopathologies of time‘ – a paper that opens up the tole of time both a methodological tool and a site or clinical focus in early 20th-century psychiatry. Here she talks to Rhodri Hayward about the psychopathological functions of time in this period.

Rhodri Hayward (RH): Allegra, in your article, you draw the reader’s attention to a neglected tradition in Western psychiatry which sought to explore the connections between mental disturbance and the corruption of time consciousness.  In particular, you draw attention to the work of Henri Bergson and Eugène Minkowski showing how they explored the tensions between lived time and clock time to build what you call a ‘futurist’ psychiatry.  As I understand it, this contrasts with the contemporary psychotherapies of Freudian psychoanalysis and Janet’s dynamic psychiatry.  Whereas psychoanalysis is concerned with an individual’s inability to integrate their past, and Pierre Janet’s methods that aimed to orientate consciousness toward the present, Minkowski’s followers were concerned with the idea that patients were alienated from the future.  Could you say a little more about this ‘futurist’ psychiatry and why you think it flourished in the interwar years?

Allegra Fryxell (AF): I think it is perhaps unsurprising that a ‘futurist’ approach took root in psychiatry at the same time as a variety of avant-garde movements like Italian Futurism were engaging with ideas about the future. Many historians have understood interwar Europe and North America as a period characterised by dramatic social changes following the Great War, which catalysed a discussion about the ‘shape’ of possible new futures — particularly in Europe, where the revolutions of 1917-1919 ushered in a period of political instability. The futurist emphasis of the phenomenological psychiatrists upon whom I focus in this article is a natural facet of this socio-historical context. That being said, I don’t think the history of psychiatry that I am attempting to unravel is simply an interwar phenomenon. Psychological research on time started in mid-nineteenth-century experiments on the time of responses to physical stimuli as well as memory. Interwar phenomenological psychology was in conversation with these earlier developments as well as concurrent discussions about time in philosophy and science — like Einstein’s theory of relativity or Bergson’s philosophy of duration — in which time had occupied a central place since at least the 1890s. We need only think of Marcel Proust’s À la recherche du temps perdu (1913), James Joyce’s Ulysses (1922), or Virginia Woolf’s Mrs Dalloway (1925) to see evidence of this temporally focused discourse in modern literature.

Indeed, ‘Time with a Capital T’ (as contemporaries wrote) was a major focal point of discussion transcending physics or philosophy in western culture. Historians have admirably uncovered some aspects of this phenomenon, including Jimena Canales’ work on ‘microtimes’ and the debate between Einstein and Bergson in 1922 (in A Tenth of a Second: A History (2009) and The Physicist and the Philosopher (2016)), or Vanessa Ogle’s masterful exploration of the uneven implementation of standardised clock time, The Global Transformation of Time, 1870-1950 (2015). My own work, however, complicates the long-standing historical interest in the proliferation of clock-time and time standardisation by uncovering a deeper and far more complex debate about time across the arts and sciences. The phenomenological psychiatry that I bring to the fore here is part of a larger project in which I attempt to tease out a conception of time that challenges or resists the simple quantification of clock-time in philosophy, drama, music, and science fiction—I’m hoping to address sociology and economics, too, in the final monograph!

What I find especially interesting is how deeply this ‘time discourse’ penetrates late-nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century understandings of lived experience and the universe. While we tend to view ‘modern’ time in terms of relativity theory or the triumph of clock-time (tied to experiences of industrialization and now globalization or the information economy), my research suggests that a far deeper exploration of what it means to be-in-the-world was at play in this period (thus we must read the phenomenological tradition in Western psychiatry as a counterpart to intellectual approaches such as the philosophies of Edmund Husserl or Martin Heidegger). Part of my goal is therefore to bring psychiatrists such as Minkowski into discussion when considering the zeitgeist of the 1880s through the 1930s, in order to demonstrate how time was central to modernist understandings of the world—not simply in the form of ‘clock-time’ or linear ‘acceleration’, as Gerhard Dohrn-van Rossum, Michael O’Malley, Hartmut Rosa and others have argued. The futurity at work, then, in interwar phenomenological psychiatry is part of a broader discussion regarding the meaning of time: what is it? How do we experience it? How do temporal disorders cause illness? And what constitutes a ‘temporal disorder’? The ‘futural’ answer put forth by psychiatrists like Minkowski and Erwin Straus is not exclusively about the future—it is about integrating or orienting oneself in time towards the future, while remaining mindful of the present and in full possession of the past. It is their resolution to address all three dimensions of time that distinguishes their approach from the past-orientation of Freudian psychoanalysis or the presentist discussions of Pierre Janet.

RH: You quote Wyndham Lewis on the ‘time mind’ of the interwar public but arguably contemporary academia shares this same ‘time mind’ with a rich stream of books, special issues, conferences and seminars on temporality appearing now, as well as a formidable array of conceptual tools for addressing time (multiple modernities, chronotypes, pluritemporality, heterotemporality etc.).

AF: Most certainly! I started my doctoral research before temporality had become the current vogue in academic research, so I find the recent focus on time simultaneously surprising and enriching. As I suggested in my recent article on modern time in Past & Present, part of the attraction to time lies in the fact that the history of Western modernity has been entangled with the fetishisation of controlling or measuring time since the Enlightenment — one might therefore interpret the resurgence of time within the academy as another feature of this aspiration to define time. On the other hand, I think the ‘temporal turn’ is a natural product of the various ‘turns’ in historical research; linguistic, cultural, and particularly spatial. It makes sense that, after scholars have attempted to understand the significance ‘space’ holds in experience and theory, they have turned to its concomitant ‘time’ in seeking to understand the world. In fact, if we consider history as the discipline par excellence concerned with time, it is surprising — as Keith Moxey underscores in Visual Time: The Image in History (2013) — that historians have not questioned our epistemology of time given its centrality to our discipline and to our methodology. Working on time has made me more aware of the work that seemingly neutral labels like ‘Renaissance’, ‘early modern’ or ‘1848’ do to shape our understanding of the past. Consequently, I think the temporal turn is partly a legacy of postmodernism, encouraging us to reconsider time as a tool of historical research as well as an intrinsic part of historical experience. Everyone, after all, lives within and through time, even though our individual experiences of time are subjectively different and even though we might live within multiple simultaneous ‘time cultures’ (the religious calendars of Judaism or Islam, for example, compared to the predominantly Christian-inflected social calendars of the West; or the rhythms of semesters and birthdays, of gestation and menstruation, of childhood, ageing, and disease). If we think about the oscillation between ‘utopian’ and ‘dystopian’ views of the future in Western thought across the twentieth century, too, then the current vogue for temporality in academic research may also reflect a widespread unease or anxiety regarding the future.

RH: I’d like to come back to that idea of contemporary anxiety, but just focusing for  a moment on the growing interest in phenomenological psychiatry (in the work of Matthew Ratcliffe and Gareth Owen for instance), what role do you think that the ideas of Minkowski and Bergson have to play in psychiatry today?  I’m struck by the contrast between the current emphasis on being in the present which seems central to the contemporary mindfulness movement (see Matt Drage in HHS from last year) and to the phenomenological urge to recover a lost connection to the future.

AF: This is an excellent question, and happily I think these ideas are indeed resurfacing in psychiatry today. You are absolutely right that the mindfulness movement brings renewed attention to presence, and although it might seem ostensibly ‘presentist’, I think it harks to the same project that Minkowski et al are trying to achieve: orienting the body within time. Although mindfulness practitioners emphasise a focus on the present in meditation, mindfulness is arguably about relaxing the mind and body in order to approach the future with vitality and direction — the orientation that Minkowski and his colleagues saw lacking in individuals suffering from schizophrenia or depression. While interwar psychiatrists failed to offer a solution (unlike mindfulness practitioners), both groups are striving to understand how time shapes existence and how individuals can better relate to time in order to be healthy and successful.

As far as academic research goes, phenomenology appears to be re-entering experimental paradigms and theories in current psychology. There is a lot of recent research indicating that Minkowski’s ideas are resurfacing as alternative means of exploring psychiatric disorders, suggesting that the turn toward analytical philosophy and pharmaceutical psychiatry in the latter half of the twentieth century no longer holds validity for addressing lived experience.

RH: So on our current anxieties. You’ve drawn from people like Reinhart Koselleck and François Hartog the idea that technological modernity has led to a shrinking of the present, but I wonder if there is also a political process under way.  In reading Minkowski and his colleagues’ descriptions of patients’ alienations from the future, I’m reminded of the radical claims made by critics such as Mark Fisher and Ivor Southwood that contemporary working conditions with their inbuilt precarity create a situation in which planning ahead/or imagining a future becomes impossible.  At the same time we see similar arguments being made around the triumph of neo-liberalism (which is seen as obscuring the possibility of a radical future) and environmental degradation (which is seen as robbing us of any future at all).

AF: Undoubtedly. In fact, I would say that most histories of time focus on power and time or technology and time, thus reinforcing an emphasis on the ‘compression’ of the present and the ‘acceleration’ toward the future that is understood to be central to modernity. It has been shown that precarity — whether financial or otherwise — can halt or stymy consideration of longer durations like the future. Researchers have proven, for example, that individuals who live in poverty find it difficult to save money because they cannot adequately conceive of the future when they are focusing on making enough money to survive a 24-hour-cycle or having enough to eat (psychologist Eldar Shafir calls the cognitive effects of scarcity ‘bandwidth poverty’, and economist Sendhil Mullainathan locates the same bias in busy professionals whose stress limits effective time management). The conclusions that Minkowski and his colleagues drew from their research in the 1920s and 1930s indicate that any number of stressors can prohibit an individual from achieving ‘syntony’, their word for the temporal integration of conceptions of the past, present, and future requisite for an active and healthy life that scientists are now starting to understand as impairments in neurocognitive function. They also underscored how an inability to synchronise the time of individual experience with the tempo of social life (much as Bergson suggested the need to synchronise duration within the social fabric of daily life his philosophical writings on duration) prohibits healthy existence. If there is one lesson to be learned from this research, it is that experiences of trauma or stress — including the stressors of living within authoritarian regimes, extreme neoliberal societies, or environmental catastrophes — can have a profound impact on individual syntony. Indeed, one of my students has recently finished a dissertation on the intrinsic relationship between the pathologisation of anxiety and the rise of neoliberalism since the 1960s.

RH:  I guess the strong claim that you — and your students — are making about the relationship between social organisation and the experience of time raises a larger question around the writing of history — a question you’ve already touched upon in your reference to Keith Moxey.  If our conception of temporality is based upon a particular culture or economic structure then how might the writing of history — and the history of the human sciences — be done differently?

AF:  If we accept François Hartog’s claim that the relationship between past, present, and future determines the configurations of possible histories, then the temporal assumptions of our own culture significantly condition the possibilities of writing history in the present. When approaching my own period (roughly 1880 to 1940), attentiveness to the radically different relationship between past, present, and future has led me to interpret the seemingly ‘anachronistic’ juxtapositions of historical eras in modernist literature, for example, as a serious gesture – one that moreover resonates with the religious revivals of the nineteenth century or beliefs in the afterlife in Victorian and Edwardian spiritualism and occultism, such as theosophy. It also shifts the epistemological foundations of fields like archaeology, as my work on popular Egyptomania in British culture elucidates and offers new insight for understanding the relationship between explorations of multiverses in geometry and physics (the fourth dimension, relativity’s space-time, etc.).

Overall, the connections that are newly underscored by attending to the temporal assumptions at work in a given historical moment offer us new ways of understanding seemingly transformative moments (such as the development of relativity theory) within longer-term cultural perspectives that do not always ‘fit’ into existing paradigms (such as the surge in spiritualism following the Great War alongside the secularisation thesis). It also compels us to read our own histories in a different light. I wonder, for example, whether the determination to find examples of schisms or ruptures between epochs (like the First World War) or experiences of ‘acceleration’ in the nineteenth century – when the majority of Europeans and North Americans did not have access to new technologies like the telegraph until much later in the century – is tied to globalization and the rise of cybernetics, and thus rather more reflective of our own time culture and social anxieties.

Having said that, I suspect that I am skirting around your question rather than directly resolving it. The temporal turn behoves us to evaluate past histories from the perspective of that culture’s specific temporal assumptions and attend to how past time cultures shaped the possibilities of existence. The latter includes belief systems including science, experience of childhood and ageing, models of the body and society, and perspectives on past and future. Given the centrality of time to human experience, I think the human sciences in particular can benefit from a temporal approach to understand its disciplinary histories.

Allegra R.P Fryxell is a Trebilcock-Newton Research Fellow at Pembroke College, Cambridge. She is a cultural historian of modern Europe, focusing on the interactions between the arts and sciences in late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century France, Britain, Germany, Italy, and America.

Rhodri Hayward is Reader in History at Queen Mary University of London, and an editor at HHS.

Include everything

The December 2018 issue of The History of the Human Sciences presents a collection of essays dedicated to understanding the historical, political, moral and aesthetic issues in totalizing projects of late modernity – ‘The Total Archive: Data, Identity, Universality.’ Here the issue’s editors, Boris Jardine and Matthew Drage, discuss the origins of the project and some of their ideas about the image and pragmatics of universal knowledge.

Matthew Drage (MD): Boris, tell me a bit about how the idea for this special issue came about?

Boris Jardine (BJ): I was visiting the Max Planck Institute (MPI) for the History of Science (Berlin) in 2014, as part of the working group ‘Historicizing Big Data’ – but I was only at the MPI briefly, and when I was back in Cambridge I wanted to do something that drew on what I’d learnt there, involving some of the fantastic scholars I’d met. It seemed to me that the idea/reality of ‘The Archive/archives’ supervened on notions of ‘data’, and that there were philosophical, ethical and historical issues around classification, privacy and knowledge that became pressing when the concept of ‘totality’ came into play. I was also talking to historians in different fields – economic history, history of bio-medicine, art history/aesthetics – and wanted to do something that connected those. With some colleagues I proposed a conference at CRASSH (Centre for Research in Arts, Social Sciences and Humanities) in Cambridge, which happened in March 2015. So this has been a while germinating!

MD: I know might be is a slightly strange side of the story , but my recollection is that it was also connected to an art project that we were both involved in.

BJ: Yes, ‘UA’, or ‘Elements of Religion’ as it was originally known. That was how I/we got to the idea of the aesthetics of totality, as a (quasi) religious idea. I wrote about that in the special issue of LIMN that came out soon after the conference. But you’re better placed to explain what that project was…

MD: I’ll do my best! So at the same time that Boris was thinking about the historical questions surrounding the emergence of the first really huge data projects of the 21st century – we were both part of an Arts Council project which aimed to consider totality from a rather different perspective. We were thinking and talking about the ways in which religions sought to encompass totalities, and how the productive modes that religions often house (text-writing, ritual, song, architecture, healing practices, contemplation) are arranged to create all-encompassing institutional wholes. And we were trying to produce our own productive systems styled on religion, as a way of making and viewing artworks. John Tresch, a historian of science who influenced mine and Boris’s introduction to the special issue, writes at length how the Auguste Comte sought to create a ‘religion of positivism’ – a religion built entirely on the ideal of total human knowledge. Our work on the aesthetics of total knowledge as parts of ‘Elements of Religion’ gave us a perspective on the emergent debates about big data that we then went on to explore in the conference in 2015, and then the special issue.

BJ: So a large part of what we were/are thinking about is to do with ‘images’ of totality – that can indicate literal images, but it also has a broader meaning. Perhaps you could say something about that, and how the contributors addressed it?

MD: I think this was what I found most exciting about the contributions – the range of ways in which the authors dealt with and understood ‘images’ of totality. In the case of Judith Kaplan’s work, for example, sometimes this took the form of poetic images. Her article examines (in part) the work of a group of Russian historical linguistic scholars, who collaborated with Americans in the 1990s to attempt to uncover the deep pre-history of human language. One of the field’s founding fathers, V. M. Illich-Svitych, Kaplan tells us, pieced together a projected ‘Nostratic’ language, which, he claimed, gave birth to eight major world language groups. In the language he had devised, he composed poems. In one, he wrote,

Language is a ford through the river of Time, 

It leads us to the dwelling place of those gone ahead; 

But he does not arrive there

Who is afraid of deep water. 

I think this typifies the kind of visionary, sometimes even mystical perspective that, as the authors in this issue show, seem to emerge when people take the image of the total archive very seriously as a model for human knowledge. It seem to draw those who are involved into (and perhaps sometimes past) the limits of human subjectivity, and then to confront them, sometimes violently, with the political, moral, aesthetic and spiritual consequences. 

BJ: I love that this example is also about pragmatics. Kaplan explains how Illich-Svitych was trying to resolve quite a difficult technical issue in historical linguistics when he came up with this hypothesis about a single overarching language family. That seems to be a typical move – or one of two kinds of move: sometimes people start with a problem they want to solve and realise that they’ve come up with a procedure before coming up with a classification, at which point they end up with problems of scale, manageability, even moral issues to do with representation and ownership. This is striking in the case of Alan Lomax, as described by Whitney Laemmli. That’s also what I found with Mass-Observation. And it’s obviously a very contemporary concern in the age of social media, genetic data etc. The other direction is also interesting though: the ‘Casaubon method’, where you have a ‘key to all mythologies’ and collect or order everything within that system, or find a way to order everything in such a way that nothing can be added or taken away. Just thinking of Edward Casaubon from Middlemarch though, do you think there are important issues of gender and gendered knowledge in this collection?

MD: Something that comes through very strongly in a lot of the articles in this issue is the relationship between ambitious, utopian institution-building and patriarchal power. This is something that Jacques Derrida talks a lot about in his long essay, Archive Fever, which has a lot to say about how psychoanalysis – one of the 20th century’s defining knowledge projects – was very strongly structured by a Jewish patriarchal logic that valorises ritualised transmissions from father to son. Many of his conclusions there could, I think, be justly extended to cover the cases covered in this special issue. The dream of universal knowledge was often also a dream of extending the agency of individual men, institutions, nations, to encompass totalities which would then be pressed into their service, and a the same time used as a means of by which to draw in ever-greater quantities of data. Rebecca Lemov’s article, which describes the data-gathering practices of the American military in the South Pacific, is particularly good at showing how this masculinist, almost “conquestadorial” urge plays out in practice in the human sciences.

BJ: Another way to think about it – though maybe it raises more questions than it provides answers – is in terms of subjectivity: the archival subject, as (on the one hand) an organizer, possibly even a heroic or all-knowing organizer, then (on the other) an invisible labourer, cleaning up, sorting the data, enlisting subjects, becoming a subject (as in Mass-Observation), and finally (on the third hand?) the knowing subject – but I think this is where we kept hitting up against this idea of ‘pathology’ in totalizing projects. There is often ‘too much to know’, too much to organize, no place to start. I use the term ‘bathos’ to describe this for Mass-Observation but it’s definitely also present in Lemov’s piece in the figure of Tarev (a Micronesian person who displays behavior that baffles the measurement systems of the Americans sent to study him) and how he can’t quite find his place in the social data project run by Melford Spiro. The thing that links these is the critique of universality, which is there in our introduction and in some of the essays, but is probably best articulated in Cadence Kinsey’s piece on Camille Henrot and her work Grosse Fatigue.

MD: Maybe this brings us to an important point: there has been a lot of discussion recently, following electoral scandals in the US and in Britain, of the power of enormous data-gathering projects like those of Google and Facebook, of the political dangers of the dream of total knowledge. Shoshana Zuboff has written about this in a particularly provocative and urgent way in her recent book, Surveillance Capitalism. What do you think this special issue has to contribute to that debate? 


Bullock’s Museum, (Egyptian Hall or London Museum), Piccadilly: the interior. Coloured aquatint, 1810. Thomas Hosmer Shepherd, 1793-1864. Credit: Wellcome Collection – CC-BY.

BJ: Probably the most obvious point is that the collection of huge amounts of data is also an issue of subjectivity, so that like it or not there is a fundamental connection between the self and its ‘data doubles’, and this isn’t something that can easily be ignored or avoided. Sometimes this is because there is a direct relationship between data and possibility, like in Daniel Wilson’s article about the kinds of information insurance companies offer and the attitude towards mortality that they engendered. In that case there’s a very clear connection between self-conception, financial possibility and particular ideologies of data. In other cases the connection is less clear cut but still decisive, and this seems to hinge on that idea of ‘totality’. One thing that Zuboff brings out really well I think is the way that Surveillance Capitalism is indiscriminate in a certain sense: these companies don’t really care exactly what kind of data they can accumulate. This gives a scary sense of randomness to the kind of (radically multiple) data doubles that we are all already accumulating. It’s also a kind of positivism in reverse: the data constitute the reality, but not because there is any kind of empiricist system, rather because there are massively accumulative technologies that just happen to latch on and then re-present different parts of the world.

MD: The way you put it just there suggests that maybe what the special issue adds to the debate is an important element of reflexivity. It’s not a new idea that those who are measured are changed by the process of measurement – it’s a point that Michel Foucault has made very thoroughly. Perhaps what the authors in this issue show is that there are some marked patterns in the way large-scale knowledge projects affect the human subject when those projects aim to include absolutely everything – an ambition which has never been so nearly reached as it has been by Google. 

BJ: Definitely. There are clearly issues of the limits of these projects, what they exclude, who gets left out and so on, that are common whenever the idea of totality is brought into play. But I also think the strength of the issue is in the historical specificity of the case studies. The point in each case (I take it) is that something as seemingly universal as universality has its own complex history. So there are useful points of continuity and also discontinuity – it has to be ‘both/and’ I think.

Matthew Drage is an artist, writer and postdoctoral researcher. He lately completed his PhD at the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at Cambridge, and is now Post-Doctoral Research Fellow in the History of Art, Science and Folk Practice, at the Warburg Institue, in the School of Advanced study, University of London. 

Boris Jardine is a Leverhulme Trust Early Career Research Fellow, supported by the Isaac Newton Trust, at the Department of the History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge. His project is titled, “The Lost Museums of Cambridge Science, 1865–1936.”

Honorable Mention: Alexandra Rutherford

The editors of History of the Human Sciences are delighted to learn that Alexandra Rutherford’s ‘Surveying Rape,’ published in the journal in 2017, has received an honorable mention at the 2019 awards of the Forum for History of Human Science.

Rutherford’s article is an account of the role that social science methods play in “realizing” sexual assault, amid public discussion of (and conservative-led controversy about) the statistic that 1 in 5 women students on (US) college campus experience sexual assault. Setting aside questions of methodological validity, Rutherford shows how the survey, as a measuring device, has become central to the “ontological politics” of sexual assault. Drawing on histories of feminist social science, the article suggests that the social and political life of the survey has been a central actor in rendering sexual assault legible: “only by conceptualizing the survey as an active participant in the ontological politics of campus sexual assault,” Rutherford argues, “can we understand both the persistence of the critical conservative response to the ‘1 in 5’ statistic and its successful deployment in anti-violence policy.”

The editors would like to extend their very warmest congratulations to Professor Rutherford for this much deserved recognition. The article is free to download for rest of the month at this link.

What common nature can exist?

Elizabeth Hannon & Tim Lewens (Eds) Why we disagree about human nature. Oxford University Press, 2018. 206 pp. £30 hbk.

By Simon Jarrett

If one day a disturbingly precocious child were to ask what part you had played in the nature/ nurture war, what would you reply? Were you with the massed intellectual ranks who, since the philosopher David Hull’s ground-breaking 1986 classic ‘On Human Nature,’ have denied that there is any such thing as a common nature for all humans? Or did you join Stephen Pinker’s 2003 counter-revolution, when The Blank Slate sought to reclaim the ground for the Enlightenment, and the idea that there is something essentially the same about all humans across time, space and culture?

If you are not quite sure where you stand, or perhaps too sure where you stand, then this pleasingly eclectic collection of ten essays on human nature, and whether we can meaningfully talk about such a thing, will be of great help. Its contributors, who come from psychology, philosophy of science, social and biological anthropology, evolutionary theory, and the study of animal cognition, include human nature advocates, deniers, and sceptics. We could perhaps call the sceptics ‘so-whaters’ – they agree there may be something we can attach the label ‘human nature’ to, but query whether it really matters, or carries any explanatory weight. These people would take our (hopefully apocryphal) infant prodigy aside and say, ‘well there are some conceptual complexities here that make it quite difficult to give you a straightforward answer.’

Human nature remains, alongside consciousness, one of the great explanatory gaps, a question that permeated philosophical enquiry in antiquity, lay at the heart of Enlightenment ‘science of Man’, and now forms a central anxiety of modernity.  The over-arching problem is, in essence, this: are there traits and characteristics that are biological, and not learned or culturally acquired, which we can say form something called the nature of the human, and which not only define humans as a unified entity but also differentiate them from all other species? In which case, what on earth are they? Or: are we essentially constructed by culture, our traits and characteristics formed by experience, language, learning and social relations, and once we strip away these veneers we find no inner essence that unites us a human species, no meaningful shared oneness other than what we have made ourselves? In which case, what on earth do we mean by ‘we’?

As Hannon and Lewens’ title suggests, we all disagree about human nature and – as the final chapter warns us – are probably destined always to do so, not least because of the term’s epistemological slipperiness. However, one thing on which the contributors find consensus is that the essentialist concept of human nature – ‘that to be human is to possess a crucial “human” gene, or a distinctively “human” form of… intelligence, language, technical facility, or whatever’ (pp.2-3) – is dead. The essentialist idea was killed by Charles Darwin, because if species variation occurs across time and space then there can be nothing invariable in their form and structure, and therefore nothing that we can call a fixed, universal and unchanging ‘nature’. If humankind has adapted, evolved and varied over millions of years, and across numerous environments, what common nature can exist amongst all humans, past and present?


Relation of the human face to that of the ass, 17th C. Credit: Wellcome Collection.CC BY

The death of essentialism, however, does not mean the death of the idea of a human nature. Four essays that defend the idea begin the collection, starting with a defence by Edouard Machery of his much-assailed (including in this book) ‘nomological notion’. By this Machery means identifying typicality in human beings, traits that are common to most humans, but which do not have to be universal, and do not even have to hold evolutionary significance. He includes only traits that are demonstrably biologically evolved, and excludes cultural processes, on the grounds that just because most people learn something, this does not become an essential trait of humanness. His theory falls far short of, and explicitly rejects, essentialism, but nevertheless argues that traits of groups of typical human beings, and of individual typical humans in particular life stages, constitute something we can call human nature: it is the properties that humans tend to possess as a result of evolution.

Grant Ramsey, in his contribution, calls Machery’s theory a ‘trait-bin’ account, which essentially assembles a series of typical traits and places them together into a single bin marked ‘human nature’ while assigning all other traits, cultural, environmental or whatever, to entirely separate bins. Ramsey proposes instead a ‘trait cluster’ account which, rather than assembling a collection of natural traits, captures the complex ways in which traits are related to each other, and the patterns created over life histories by their interactions. The sum of these patterns, seen as potential developmental trajectories at various stages of life, give us human nature. As Ramsey puts it: ‘trait cluster accounts hold that human nature lies not in which traits individual humans happen to have, but in the ways the traits are exhibited over human life histories’ (p.56). This is more encompassing than Machery’s account, which excludes atypical traits, but maintains that there is a nature to be derived from an exploration of all traits and their interactions.

Karola Stotz and Paul Griffiths offer a ‘developmental systems account’ which echoes Ramsey’s but argues for the adoption of the human developmental environment into an account of human nature. They use the idea of ‘niche construction’ – whereby organisms singly and collectively modify their own niches to transform natural selection pressures – to argue that there is a uniquely human developmental niche. This is the environment created for human infants comprising parental interaction, schooling and artefacts such as tool use and language. In this sense nature is culture, and humans create the selection pressures that act on future generations. Human nature is human development, environment is as important as any biological or genomic essence.

The final advocate of a specific human nature is Cecilia Heyes, who echoes Machery in believing that there are certain traits that comprise human nature, but builds into this a theory of what she calls ‘evolutionary causal essentialism’, a key element of which is ‘natural pedagogy’. This sees the teaching of human infants not as an exclusively cultural phenomenon, but as a heritable system whereby nature makes human infants receptive to teaching signals.

The reply of the sceptics to the notion of a ‘human nature’ begins with John Dupré’s ‘process perspective’, which argues that a human cannot be considered as a thing or substance (and therefore something which has a nature) but is rather a process. Humans comprise a life cycle, and are associated with different properties or traits at its different stages. In their very early stages, for example, and often in their latest stages, humans lack language. We cannot, therefore, associate humans with a fixed set of properties; they are instead a plastic process responding to changing environments, and sometimes changing those environments themselves. We could, if we like, call this process itself ‘human nature’ but such a ‘descriptive venture’ would carry little conceptual weight.

Kim Stereny’s ‘Sceptical reflections on human nature’ argues, in similar vein, that even if there is some set of traits shared by most humans – what he calls a ‘cognitive suite’ – describing these as human nature is ‘bland and uninformative’ and lacks any explanatory power. Such a descriptive account of human nature is little more than a ‘field-guide’ to our species – in which case, Serelny asks, do we need it?


SEM human hair. Credit: David Gregory & Debbie MarshallCC BY

Kevin Laland and Gillian Brown recommend that the concept of human nature simply be abandoned. It is, they argue, socially constructed in a number of ways. Evolutionary history is not easily separated into biological and cultural evolutionary processes, since each is dynamic and interacts with the other. Like Stotz and Griffiths they recognise the uniqueness and importance of the developmental niche in the human process, but see it as product of inseparable internal and constructive processes which cannot be incorporated into a theory of an evolved nature. More important is to build an understanding of the human condition over developmental and evolutionary timescales, in all its diversity and multiple processes.

Peter Richerson’s survey of major theorists from Darwin to Pinker rejects any form of strong human nature claim. The later theorists, he notes, all have a strong commitment to the ‘Modern Synthesis’ – a term popularised by Julian Huxley in 1942 – which, in very simple terms, seeks to combine evolution and heredity. For Richerson, the Modern Synthesis account of human nature, with its rejection of the fundamental role of cultural evolutionary processes against overwhelming evidence, has reached the end of the line.

Christina Toren weighs in with an anthropological broadside against the notion that some traits are products of nature rather than culture. Based on her own ethnographic studies, she calls for the rejection of notions of both nature and culture, and calls instead for a focus on ontogeny – the development of the human organism over its life cycle, and within its environments and social relations. Toren’s model focuses on the microhistorical processes that build each individual: ‘mind is a function of the whole person that is constituted over time in intersubjective relations with others in the environing world.’ No ‘nature’ can capture such complexity.

The collection ends with Maria Kronfelder’s elegant interrogation of the term ‘nature’, and the power relations lurking within its appropriation by intellectuals seeking to lay out a domain of study they can claim as their own. This welcome historicization of the subject begins in Greek antiquity and journeys through the Enlightenment, to the advent of heredity (which, Kronfelder notes, shifted from the adjective ‘hereditary’ to a nominal noun defining itself as a scientific field), and finally to Machery’s nomological account, where the book began. In each case the word ‘nature’ is used to denote a field-defining phenomenon in need of explanation – explanations which those using the term saw themselves as having the authority and capacity to produce. It was also used in contradistinction: to the supranatural, to nurture, to culture, and to other enemies which the ‘nature’ power claim could dismiss as irrelevant. Nature, in these claims, was ‘always what could be taken for granted… solid, authoritative’ and carrying some form of objective reality (p.202).

It falls to Kronfelder to explain why ‘we’ disagree, and will probably always disagree, about human nature. Firstly, when talking about our own nature, we fall into what she calls ‘essentialist traps’ involving normalcy and normativity, that we do not apply when more carefully describing other species. Secondly, we have traditionally tried to identify ‘what it means to be human’, which has led us to apply to human nature a description of what characterises our in-group, consequently dehumanising out-groups by placing them outside human signifiers. In this context, different human groups will always disagree about what it means to be human, and thus about human nature. Finally, we load the term ‘human nature’ with too many contradictory and incompatible meanings. Do we want it to be a description of a bundle of properties, a set of explanatory factors, or a boundary-determining classification? It can never be all three, but precisely which epistemological duty it is being asked to perform at any one time in any one context is often obfuscated. We will never agree, because we are arguing from parallel starting points that are invisible to one another.

At the heart of the human nature debate lies, since the collapse of the essentialist view, not only the issue of whether there is such a thing, but also whether such a thing is worth thinking about. If the account of human nature spreads so widely, becoming the set of genetic, epigenetic and environmental traits that we can observe in humans, then does it just become a conceptual mush, consisting of everything that humans ever do or experience? If purely descriptive, then does it lack any explanatory power, thereby rendering it conceptually worthless?  Or is there something about our nature that binds us, and is worth knowing? This is a defining issue for those who practice or study the human sciences, which after all is the study of humans from diverse perspectives. The collection is a hugely helpful trek across much of the best of the current scholarship, and an elegant framing of the key debates, for which the editors should be congratulated.


Simon Jarrett is a visiting lecturer and honorary research fellow at Birkbeck, University of London. His monograph on the history of ‘idiocy’ will be published in 2020. With Jan Walmsley, he is co-editor of Intellectual disability in the twentieth century: transnational perspectives on people policy and practice. (Policy Press 2019). His current research is on theories of consciousness in relation to the deficient mind.

A “Metaphysics of the Dunces”

Jason Ā. Josephson-Storm. The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2017; xiv + 411 pp. $96.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-226-40322-9; $32.00 (paperback), ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.

by Andreas Sommer

If recent surveys of belief in magic are accurate, there is a good chance that you either hold some variant of these beliefs yourself, or that you may be puzzled by some otherwise secular-minded colleague, friend, or family member who does. Jason Ā. Josephson-Storm might not be a believer in spirits himself, but reveals toward the end of this remarkable book a significant factor in his choice of becoming a religious scholar: his grandmother Felicitas Goodman, the noted anthropologist who caused quite a stir when she openly confessed her commitments to shamanism. An expert of East Asian religions, Josephson-Storm’s previous cross-cultural studies have certainly prepared him well to tackle vexing questions regarding the Western occult. But it is perhaps especially owing to a deep respect for his heretical ancestor that The Myth of Disenchantment is marked by a refreshingly even-handed approach which neither mocks nor advocates unorthodox beliefs. Instead, Josephson-Storm makes a bold and sincere effort to come to grips with hidden continuities of magic in often surprising places, and the persistence of Western normative assertions of the disenchantment of the world as the flip-side of that puzzle.

Regarding the latter issue, the book can be considered a historical test of the actual adherence to basic naturalistic proscriptions in the humanities and human sciences. After all, as Josephson-Storm reminds us, Max Weber’s famous verdict of disenchantment is often misunderstood as motivated by a normative agenda itself. The introduction to the book formulates a fruitful principal method and rationale: to “investigate the least likely people – the very theorists of modernity as disenchantment – and show how they worked out various insights inside an occult context, in a social world overflowing with spirits and magic, and how the weirdness of that world generated so much normativity” (p. 6). While the focus of the book is on what Josephson-Storm calls the human sciences (a term which is perhaps somewhat problematically equated with the German Geisteswissenschaften, ibid.), the significance of older popular histories assuming the inherent opposition between magic and the natural sciences is also acknowledged. Among the refuting instances enlisted by the author are the familiar occult preoccupations of figureheads of the scientific revolution such as Francis Bacon, Robert Boyle, and Isaac Newton, as well as more original observations on mediumistic experiments by icons of modern ‘naturalistic’ science like Marie Curie and Pierre Curie.

Chapter 1, “Enchanted (Post) Modernity”, sets the stage by taking stock of sociological findings which document the current prevalence of occult beliefs in secular Western societies. The upshot again upsets popular assumptions and categories, including the habit of using occult beliefs as a shorthand for religion, and the view that ‘occultism’ always springs from the same politically reactionary sources which have brought about what some have diagnosed as a ‘post-truth’ society: traditional Christianity continues to decline while belief in magic is on the rise, and political affiliation appears to be as poor a predictor of occultist sympathies as education. An historiographically crucial point is that suppressions of magic do not self-evidently express anti-spiritual motifs. On the contrary, once we check the concrete means by which magic has been concealed in plain sight, it turns out that more often than not it has cancelled itself out through its own competing modes. Puritan prohibitions of magic, for instance, were not due to scepticism but naked fears of devils. (Or to use a recent example, think of pro-Trump evangelists responding with protective prayers to public appeals by self-identifying witches to bring down the President through sorcery.)

The remaining nine chapters sketch continuities of magic in major thinkers since the sixteenth century, and bear out these insights and arguments by reconstructing previously understudied currents in the formation of modern Western intellectual traditions. Drawing on personal correspondence and overlooked passages in often canonical writings of architects of ‘naturalistic’ modernity, Josephson-Storm re-enchants parts of critical theory and Freudian psychoanalysis in due course. He convincingly argues that to understand the origins of modern disciplines ranging from religious studies and sociology to linguistics and anthropology, we need to acknowledge that foundational scholars such as Max Müller, Ferdinand de Saussure, Edward B. Tylor, James Frazer and Max Weber systematically grappled with revivals of magical traditions and large-scale occult movements such as spiritualism and Indian Theosophy. This they did not as prophets of ‘scientific materialism’, but often on the basis of sustained reflection on the kinship of magic with science, and a genuine reverence for mystical and pantheistic traditions.

Josephson-Storm’s ingenious method – to search for magic in the most unlikely places – is also brought to fruition in his reconstruction of parapsychological studies by members of the Vienna Circle of logical positivism. In apparent contradiction with standard portrayals of Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Hahn as undertakers of metaphysics in science, they in fact shared a sustained curiosity in medium-istic and poltergeist-related phenomena. By no means the first to reveal this perplexing side of the Vienna Circle’s history, Josephson-Storm provides the most comprehensive account currently available in English.

Regarding the links between occultism and politics, Josephson-Storm in no way downplays the occult entanglements of Nazism. By recovering the significance of magic and mysticism in a wide range of left-leaning and Jewish thinkers, however, he puts another hefty nail in the coffin of outdated but still fashionable notions of ‘occultism’ as a necessary condition of fascism. Not least, by reminding us of the racist origins of anthropological theories which explained widespread interest in spiritualism and other ‘vulgar’ forms of magic as morbid relapses into ‘savage’ evolutionary stages, the author confronts us with some previously obscured unsavoury aspects of the suppression of magic.

In the face of the vast materials covered, some problems of detail might be inevitable. While I was glad to see the philosopher Carl du Prel being rescued from oblivion, I would disagree with Josephson-Storm’s assumption that The Philosophy of Mysticism, or indeed any of his works, were actually concerned with mysticism in the commonly accepted meaning of the term. Du Prel was not really interested in the unio mystica as a defining feature of mystical experience, and his rather loose deployment of Mystik as a synonym for spiritualism, occultism, and what would later be known as parapsychology, provoked criticisms even from some of his supporters. Du Prel’s explicit goal was to enlist supposed transcendental functions of the mind such as telepathy and clairvoyance for his model of the self, which was supposed to guarantee personal survival as a precondition for spiritualism. The statement that “philosophers and theologians like Karl Joel and Otto Pfleiderer followed du Prel in discussing the union of mysticism and philosophical thought” (p. 191) therefore needs to be qualified, as neither Joel nor Pfleiderer were known to have maintained sympathies for investigations of occult phenomena, let alone for spiritualism. A closer look at oppositions to spiritualism could have introduced an additional layer of analysis and a more vivid illustration of the important argument that the apparent decline of magic was often a result of the suppression of its ‘vulgar’ forms by protagonists adhering to ‘higher’ notions such as mysticism proper.

A related issue that Josephson-Storm touches upon but which also may have deserved further discussion is the conceptual and pragmatic ambivalence of modern continuities of Renaissance natural magic like telepathy. After all, while spiritualist authors like du Prel marshalled telepathy as supposed evidence for the mind’s dual citizenship in a co-existing physical and spirit world, materialist and positivist psychical researchers like Charles Richet, Albert von Schrenck-Notzing, and Julian Ochorowicz rejected spiritualism on the basis of the view that its phenomena could be explained by telepathy, clairvoyance and telekinesis of the living. Moreover, they doubted that these psychic phenomena had inherently spiritual implications at all.

Josephson-Storm is to be commended for his reconstruction of Sigmund Freud’s growing belief in telepathy, and for trying to make sense of his reading of du Prel. Yet while it is technically correct to state that, in embracing telepathy, du Prel and Freud “shared more than the classical narrative would admit” (p. 181), their juxtaposition again misses an opportunity to illustrate that telepathy was not always interpreted as an inherently spiritual let alone ‘magical’ phenomenon. Josephson-Storm concedes that “it seems unlikely Freud ever came to believe in spirits” (p. 203), but I would also highly doubt that Freud seriously considered non-physicalist interpretations of telepathy that imbued it with spiritual meaning. Similar reservations apply to remarks about the assumed openness to belief in spirits by members of the Vienna Circle (p. 258, but see the qualification on p. 268), whose interpretation of the weird phenomena some of them came to believe in were, I think, dictated by sentiments akin to Theodor Adorno’s notion of spiritualism as the supposed ‘metaphysics of the dunces’. Moreover, while William James is occasionally mentioned, a short discussion of James’s experiments with various mediums throughout his career could have further illustrated the point that even psychical researchers sympathetic to spiritualism struggled to interpret its reported phenomena as evidence of the ‘spirit hypothesis’.

And here I have to admit I found the omission of psychology before Freud and Jung unfortunate. James is cited as a scholar of religion, but he was also the instigator of the American psychological profession, who also happened to be a psychical researcher. Together with another ‘professionalizer’ of psychology, Théodore Flournoy in Switzerland, James was heavily indebted to the inventor of the term telepathy, Frederic W. H. Myers. The latter doesn’t appear in the book at all, while Flournoy is mentioned in passing only in regard to Ferdinand de Saussure’s involvement in Flournoy’s psychological studies of mediumistic trance productions. Moreover, the dismissal of both spiritualism and psychical research by Wilhelm Wundt as the ‘father’ of professionalized psychology in Germany could have nicely illustrated a psychological ‘standard mode’ in the war against magic discussed in Josephson-Storm’s treatment of Tylor and Frazer: like other border-guards of professionalized psychology, Wundt relied on these anthropological frameworks to discredit uncritical spiritualism along with serious attempts to test and interpret its alleged phenomena. Moreover, Wundt’s anti-occultist polemics, in light of his assertions that his own psychological project was indebted to a quasi-mystical experience as well as the writings of mystics like Jakob Böhme, is another important example that would have served to support a main thesis of the book.

An appreciation of the significance of the occult during psychology’s professionalization might also have prevented the problematic statement that “for all the polemical attacks against superstition and magic, disenchanting efforts were only sporadically enforced within the disciplines” (p. 16). The ‘psychology of paranormal belief’, which I would describe as an industry with the sole intent of policing metaphysical deviance, is a direct outgrowth of polemical strategies by psychologists like Wundt and Joseph Jastrow. Historical contexts and debunkers’ own metaphysical commitments may have changed drastically, but orthodox psychology’s axiomatic dismissals of belief in magic and spirits still serve to shield the profession’s public image from ongoing associations with the occult in marginalized disciplines such as parapsychology.

Such quibbles aside, in my view The Myth of Disenchantment still stands head and shoulders above recent historical monographs on the modern Western occult. With its focus on continuities of magic in unexpected places, and demonstrations of how enchantment has often undermined itself through competing modes, a major distinguishing feature of the study is a complete lack of timidity, delving as it does straight into the heart of fiercely contested issues. Drawing on an impressive wealth of primary sources in various languages, Josephson-Storm shows a sure instinct for hidden treasures, and recovers significant associations of canonical figures with important, but now obscure, actors and ideas. Not all of his insights are fully unpacked, but the overall level of rigour and balance displayed by Josephson-Storm is so rare that I just might try my luck at sorcery, if that’s what it takes to make him continue this line of research.

Andreas Sommer is an independent scholar working on the history of the sciences and their cross-links with magic. His Wellcome Trust-funded doctoral thesis (UCL, 2013) reconstructed the formation of modern psychology in response to psychical research in Europe and the US, and won a Young Scholar Award from the International Union of History and Philosophy of Science and Technology. He held research posts at Cambridge University and has published various journal articles and chapters in edited books. He is currently working on a monograph expanding his earlier findings while running Forbidden Histories, a website distilling academic work in the history of science and magic to a broad, educated audience.