A “Metaphysics of the Dunces”

Jason Ā. Josephson-Storm. The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2017; xiv + 411 pp. $96.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-226-40322-9; $32.00 (paperback), ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.

by Andreas Sommer

If recent surveys of belief in magic are accurate, there is a good chance that you either hold some variant of these beliefs yourself, or that you may be puzzled by some otherwise secular-minded colleague, friend, or family member who does. Jason Ā. Josephson-Storm might not be a believer in spirits himself, but reveals toward the end of this remarkable book a significant factor in his choice of becoming a religious scholar: his grandmother Felicitas Goodman, the noted anthropologist who caused quite a stir when she openly confessed her commitments to shamanism. An expert of East Asian religions, Josephson-Storm’s previous cross-cultural studies have certainly prepared him well to tackle vexing questions regarding the Western occult. But it is perhaps especially owing to a deep respect for his heretical ancestor that The Myth of Disenchantment is marked by a refreshingly even-handed approach which neither mocks nor advocates unorthodox beliefs. Instead, Josephson-Storm makes a bold and sincere effort to come to grips with hidden continuities of magic in often surprising places, and the persistence of Western normative assertions of the disenchantment of the world as the flip-side of that puzzle.

Regarding the latter issue, the book can be considered a historical test of the actual adherence to basic naturalistic proscriptions in the humanities and human sciences. After all, as Josephson-Storm reminds us, Max Weber’s famous verdict of disenchantment is often misunderstood as motivated by a normative agenda itself. The introduction to the book formulates a fruitful principal method and rationale: to “investigate the least likely people – the very theorists of modernity as disenchantment – and show how they worked out various insights inside an occult context, in a social world overflowing with spirits and magic, and how the weirdness of that world generated so much normativity” (p. 6). While the focus of the book is on what Josephson-Storm calls the human sciences (a term which is perhaps somewhat problematically equated with the German Geisteswissenschaften, ibid.), the significance of older popular histories assuming the inherent opposition between magic and the natural sciences is also acknowledged. Among the refuting instances enlisted by the author are the familiar occult preoccupations of figureheads of the scientific revolution such as Francis Bacon, Robert Boyle, and Isaac Newton, as well as more original observations on mediumistic experiments by icons of modern ‘naturalistic’ science like Marie Curie and Pierre Curie.

Chapter 1, “Enchanted (Post) Modernity”, sets the stage by taking stock of sociological findings which document the current prevalence of occult beliefs in secular Western societies. The upshot again upsets popular assumptions and categories, including the habit of using occult beliefs as a shorthand for religion, and the view that ‘occultism’ always springs from the same politically reactionary sources which have brought about what some have diagnosed as a ‘post-truth’ society: traditional Christianity continues to decline while belief in magic is on the rise, and political affiliation appears to be as poor a predictor of occultist sympathies as education. An historiographically crucial point is that suppressions of magic do not self-evidently express anti-spiritual motifs. On the contrary, once we check the concrete means by which magic has been concealed in plain sight, it turns out that more often than not it has cancelled itself out through its own competing modes. Puritan prohibitions of magic, for instance, were not due to scepticism but naked fears of devils. (Or to use a recent example, think of pro-Trump evangelists responding with protective prayers to public appeals by self-identifying witches to bring down the President through sorcery.)

The remaining nine chapters sketch continuities of magic in major thinkers since the sixteenth century, and bear out these insights and arguments by reconstructing previously understudied currents in the formation of modern Western intellectual traditions. Drawing on personal correspondence and overlooked passages in often canonical writings of architects of ‘naturalistic’ modernity, Josephson-Storm re-enchants parts of critical theory and Freudian psychoanalysis in due course. He convincingly argues that to understand the origins of modern disciplines ranging from religious studies and sociology to linguistics and anthropology, we need to acknowledge that foundational scholars such as Max Müller, Ferdinand de Saussure, Edward B. Tylor, James Frazer and Max Weber systematically grappled with revivals of magical traditions and large-scale occult movements such as spiritualism and Indian Theosophy. This they did not as prophets of ‘scientific materialism’, but often on the basis of sustained reflection on the kinship of magic with science, and a genuine reverence for mystical and pantheistic traditions.

Josephson-Storm’s ingenious method – to search for magic in the most unlikely places – is also brought to fruition in his reconstruction of parapsychological studies by members of the Vienna Circle of logical positivism. In apparent contradiction with standard portrayals of Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Hahn as undertakers of metaphysics in science, they in fact shared a sustained curiosity in medium-istic and poltergeist-related phenomena. By no means the first to reveal this perplexing side of the Vienna Circle’s history, Josephson-Storm provides the most comprehensive account currently available in English.

Regarding the links between occultism and politics, Josephson-Storm in no way downplays the occult entanglements of Nazism. By recovering the significance of magic and mysticism in a wide range of left-leaning and Jewish thinkers, however, he puts another hefty nail in the coffin of outdated but still fashionable notions of ‘occultism’ as a necessary condition of fascism. Not least, by reminding us of the racist origins of anthropological theories which explained widespread interest in spiritualism and other ‘vulgar’ forms of magic as morbid relapses into ‘savage’ evolutionary stages, the author confronts us with some previously obscured unsavoury aspects of the suppression of magic.

In the face of the vast materials covered, some problems of detail might be inevitable. While I was glad to see the philosopher Carl du Prel being rescued from oblivion, I would disagree with Josephson-Storm’s assumption that The Philosophy of Mysticism, or indeed any of his works, were actually concerned with mysticism in the commonly accepted meaning of the term. Du Prel was not really interested in the unio mystica as a defining feature of mystical experience, and his rather loose deployment of Mystik as a synonym for spiritualism, occultism, and what would later be known as parapsychology, provoked criticisms even from some of his supporters. Du Prel’s explicit goal was to enlist supposed transcendental functions of the mind such as telepathy and clairvoyance for his model of the self, which was supposed to guarantee personal survival as a precondition for spiritualism. The statement that “philosophers and theologians like Karl Joel and Otto Pfleiderer followed du Prel in discussing the union of mysticism and philosophical thought” (p. 191) therefore needs to be qualified, as neither Joel nor Pfleiderer were known to have maintained sympathies for investigations of occult phenomena, let alone for spiritualism. A closer look at oppositions to spiritualism could have introduced an additional layer of analysis and a more vivid illustration of the important argument that the apparent decline of magic was often a result of the suppression of its ‘vulgar’ forms by protagonists adhering to ‘higher’ notions such as mysticism proper.

A related issue that Josephson-Storm touches upon but which also may have deserved further discussion is the conceptual and pragmatic ambivalence of modern continuities of Renaissance natural magic like telepathy. After all, while spiritualist authors like du Prel marshalled telepathy as supposed evidence for the mind’s dual citizenship in a co-existing physical and spirit world, materialist and positivist psychical researchers like Charles Richet, Albert von Schrenck-Notzing, and Julian Ochorowicz rejected spiritualism on the basis of the view that its phenomena could be explained by telepathy, clairvoyance and telekinesis of the living. Moreover, they doubted that these psychic phenomena had inherently spiritual implications at all.

Josephson-Storm is to be commended for his reconstruction of Sigmund Freud’s growing belief in telepathy, and for trying to make sense of his reading of du Prel. Yet while it is technically correct to state that, in embracing telepathy, du Prel and Freud “shared more than the classical narrative would admit” (p. 181), their juxtaposition again misses an opportunity to illustrate that telepathy was not always interpreted as an inherently spiritual let alone ‘magical’ phenomenon. Josephson-Storm concedes that “it seems unlikely Freud ever came to believe in spirits” (p. 203), but I would also highly doubt that Freud seriously considered non-physicalist interpretations of telepathy that imbued it with spiritual meaning. Similar reservations apply to remarks about the assumed openness to belief in spirits by members of the Vienna Circle (p. 258, but see the qualification on p. 268), whose interpretation of the weird phenomena some of them came to believe in were, I think, dictated by sentiments akin to Theodor Adorno’s notion of spiritualism as the supposed ‘metaphysics of the dunces’. Moreover, while William James is occasionally mentioned, a short discussion of James’s experiments with various mediums throughout his career could have further illustrated the point that even psychical researchers sympathetic to spiritualism struggled to interpret its reported phenomena as evidence of the ‘spirit hypothesis’.

And here I have to admit I found the omission of psychology before Freud and Jung unfortunate. James is cited as a scholar of religion, but he was also the instigator of the American psychological profession, who also happened to be a psychical researcher. Together with another ‘professionalizer’ of psychology, Théodore Flournoy in Switzerland, James was heavily indebted to the inventor of the term telepathy, Frederic W. H. Myers. The latter doesn’t appear in the book at all, while Flournoy is mentioned in passing only in regard to Ferdinand de Saussure’s involvement in Flournoy’s psychological studies of mediumistic trance productions. Moreover, the dismissal of both spiritualism and psychical research by Wilhelm Wundt as the ‘father’ of professionalized psychology in Germany could have nicely illustrated a psychological ‘standard mode’ in the war against magic discussed in Josephson-Storm’s treatment of Tylor and Frazer: like other border-guards of professionalized psychology, Wundt relied on these anthropological frameworks to discredit uncritical spiritualism along with serious attempts to test and interpret its alleged phenomena. Moreover, Wundt’s anti-occultist polemics, in light of his assertions that his own psychological project was indebted to a quasi-mystical experience as well as the writings of mystics like Jakob Böhme, is another important example that would have served to support a main thesis of the book.

An appreciation of the significance of the occult during psychology’s professionalization might also have prevented the problematic statement that “for all the polemical attacks against superstition and magic, disenchanting efforts were only sporadically enforced within the disciplines” (p. 16). The ‘psychology of paranormal belief’, which I would describe as an industry with the sole intent of policing metaphysical deviance, is a direct outgrowth of polemical strategies by psychologists like Wundt and Joseph Jastrow. Historical contexts and debunkers’ own metaphysical commitments may have changed drastically, but orthodox psychology’s axiomatic dismissals of belief in magic and spirits still serve to shield the profession’s public image from ongoing associations with the occult in marginalized disciplines such as parapsychology.

Such quibbles aside, in my view The Myth of Disenchantment still stands head and shoulders above recent historical monographs on the modern Western occult. With its focus on continuities of magic in unexpected places, and demonstrations of how enchantment has often undermined itself through competing modes, a major distinguishing feature of the study is a complete lack of timidity, delving as it does straight into the heart of fiercely contested issues. Drawing on an impressive wealth of primary sources in various languages, Josephson-Storm shows a sure instinct for hidden treasures, and recovers significant associations of canonical figures with important, but now obscure, actors and ideas. Not all of his insights are fully unpacked, but the overall level of rigour and balance displayed by Josephson-Storm is so rare that I just might try my luck at sorcery, if that’s what it takes to make him continue this line of research.

Andreas Sommer is an independent scholar working on the history of the sciences and their cross-links with magic. His Wellcome Trust-funded doctoral thesis (UCL, 2013) reconstructed the formation of modern psychology in response to psychical research in Europe and the US, and won a Young Scholar Award from the International Union of History and Philosophy of Science and Technology. He held research posts at Cambridge University and has published various journal articles and chapters in edited books. He is currently working on a monograph expanding his earlier findings while running Forbidden Histories, a website distilling academic work in the history of science and magic to a broad, educated audience.

Foxes v. Lions

Steve Fuller. Post-Truth: Knowledge as a Power Game; New York: Anthem Press; 218 pages; paperback $39.95; ISBN: 978-1-78308-694-8

by Steve Baxi

A consistent problem in the journalistic discourse on post-truth is the confusion between the recent phenomenon of post-truth and some historically justifiable, apolitical, entirely objective Truth – the latter having been, on some level, eclipsed by the former. Indeed, this is precisely how the Oxford English Dictionary understands post-truth, and thus the focus in mainstream media outlets and contemporary studies of truth have focused on the contentions between Truth and post-truth. However, this understanding misses the relationships of power and conditions of possibility for knowledge with respect to truth – power relations and conditions we can claim to value in research fields that place the pursuit of truth over the recent, overblown idea of Truth.

In the face of academic experts, Brexit, and social media, Steve Fuller argues that post-truth is “a deep feature of at least Western intellectual life, bringing together issues of politics, science and judgement in ways which established authorities have traditionally wished to be separate” (2018, 6). Fuller’s Post-Truth: Knowledge as a Power Game attempts to provide a set of case studies of post-truth in academia, as well as in contemporary political movements, to establish the historical character of post-truth, or what he calls a post-truth history of post-truth.

The book is divided into seven chapters, each examining Fuller’s own previously developed concepts and social epistemological stances on expertise, philosophy, sociology, and science and technology studies. Fuller especially draws on Vilfredo Pareto’s distinction between “lions” and “foxes” to help set up the tensions in his case studies. Where the lions play by the rules of the game, the foxes attempt to change the rules, but do so such that the lions believe themselves to be following the very same rules they have always followed. Fuller’s approach here is loosely genealogical, perhaps even Foucauldian, as he attempts to, at least initially, present us with a history of the present.


Two lions snarling at each other. Colour process print after Sakai Hōitsu. CC BY.Credit: Wellcome Collection

While Fuller coins various concepts, the most important appears to be modal power which he defines as “control over what can be true or false, which is reflected in institutions about what is possible, impossible, necessary and contingent” (2018, 188). Modal power mirrors the historical discourse on systems of exclusion, the most powerful of which is the will to know, here reconfigured to be part of the military-industrial will to know (more on this below). This form of power is intended not only to explain how the moves of the “lions” and “foxes” become possible, but also how the academic fields they inhabit are growing, changing, accepting or now rejecting certain paradigms of truth.

While commentary on post-truth’s relationship to Brexit and the 2016 US presidential election has largely understood post-truth as a rejection of the facts, Fuller provides a more complex account. He asks: if these events are the outcome of a certain discourse of rules, where were these rules crafted? How might we even think of Plato, in one of Fuller’s most provocative statements, as the original post-truth philosopher? And how does this change our view of the present? Fuller especially analyses Brexit via his long-standing anti-expertise approach to social epistemology. This allows him to read Brexit as a phenomenon incited by parliamentary elites distinct from the ethical values and strategies identified in wider public opinion. Fuller concludes from this a resurgence of a “general will” in democracy. Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s general will represents a sense of shared identity: to challenge me is not merely to challenge my opinion, but the very identity I share in, and the traditions I identify with. In the case of Brexit, this is how people come to rally around nationhood. In the case of academia, it is seen in the hard-lined alignment with unchanging paradigms of thought, where the act of placing a footnote is a way of counting yourself amongst a group with a political identity. Fuller asks where this growing predilection for academic politics came from. He thus dovetails into a genealogy of academic philosophy

Academics, Fuller argues, while claiming to be in pursuit of truth, or what Michel Foucault (borrowing from Nietzsche) would call savoir, have in fact, since Plato, been entrenched in what is only now referred to as Post-Truth.[ref] Foucault, Michel. “Appendix: The Discourse on Language.” The Archaeology of Knowledge, 220. Trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith. New York: Vintage Books, 2010. 215-237.[/ref] This claim is tried into Fuller’s concept of modal power, which is an account of how, collectively, any discourse becomes a discourse in the first place; post-truth is then an argument about the boundaries of discourse. Academic fields such as sociology are important because they are acutely aware of what counts as possible in terms of boundary-pushing. Where sociology had historically embraced the post-truth condition, with its analysis of how subjectivity evolves within a particular historical condition, its contemporary pursuit of a style of knowledge-making modelled on the rigid sciences fails to adequately challenge post-truth.

If post-truth and truth are separated by who decides to change the rules of the game or who follows them, sociology ought to be at some advantage. And yet sociology – and academia more widely – seems unable to confront these issues. To explain this, Fuller coins the term “military-industrial will to knowledge,” which exemplifies the pursuit of knowledge as “effective” or useful. Fuller diagnoses academia as frequently degenerating into conversations about the merits of certain principles without first identifying itself as part of the institutions of modal power.  Here, we see how goal-oriented publications, writing, or knowledge-development relates to whether one follows the rules, or changes them: i.e. whether one is a “fox” or a “lion.” A military-industrial will to know empowers certain paradigms of thought, and thus the lions are those safeguarding an unyielding sense of academic identity; the foxes are those who would challenge these norms, but the “publish or die” state of academic positions make such self-aware shifts near impossible.

Even living outside these academic norms will not necessarily solve the problem. Fuller develops the concept of ‘protscience’ to describe how individuals come to be accustomed to understandings of science. Even deviations from institutional norms still produce their own kinds of norms which are often just as dangerous and which play into the post-truth condition. Protscience most directly threads Fuller’s discussion of Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn into his more immediate interest in academia. By pulling in the philosophy of science, we begin to see how philosophy and science are not so distinct. If we take post-truth to be about how the rules change, science as the understanding of rules, and politics as their possibility via modal power, then these three “vocations” ultimately coincide with one another. Here, Fuller delivers on the fundamental premise of this text: that post-truth represents a collapse of traditional academic spheres into each other. To do philosophy is to do science; to do science is to do politics; to do politics is to do philosophy.

In general, Post-Truth is an insightful, thorough text which examines issues of truth with more nuance and clarity than most other recent works in the field. The book succeeds most overtly in its ability to present a case for why post-truth studies need be done. To understand the contemporary world, the promises of past theories, and where things go wrong in political controversy, we have to understand how post-truth in its contemporary condition unites all fields of inquiry. In this way, Fuller seems to owe much to John Dewey’s and Arthur Danto’s arguments that a solution to one problem implies a solution to all problems.[ref] Danto, Arthur C. Nietzsche as Philosopher, 24. New York: Columbia University Press, 1965 [/ref]

However, what Post-Truth lacks is a convincing case for its own need to present concepts and coinages that might go without a label. Despite a deep reading of the text, and research on Fuller’s past work, I am still unclear on why modal power is somehow different, necessary or even more precise a quantifier of power. In general, the post-Foucauldian world of academia, and certainly the audience that Fuller wishes to speak to, will be keenly aware of what we mean when we discuss the conditions for the possibility of certain concepts. Power on its own dictates an all-inclusive concept that unities the various fields that Fuller discusses, in a way that seems not to gain much by adding ‘modal’ to it.

Similarly, Fuller frequently draws on his own body of work, which wrestles with these themes of anti-institutionalism, elitism, and gate keeping.[ref]This is evident most clearly in Fuller, Steve. Social Epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988. And Fuller, Steve. The Intellectual. Cambridge, UK: Icon, 2005.[/ref] But he does so without providing us any reason to see him as one of us, outside the world of academics as we wage a war of foxes and lions on the ground. Military Industrial Will to Knowledge has quite a ring to it, as does modal power, but these concepts sometimes sound more like the academic stiffness Fuller claims to detest, and less like the tools with which we might interrogate the various values of our post-truth society.

Steve Baxi is a Graduate Student and Teaching Assistant in the Ethics and Applied Philosophy Department at the University of the North Carolina at Charlotte. He works across philosophical traditions, with a particular interest in Nietzsche and Foucault. He is currently writing on the politics of truth, and social media ethics.

Formal experimentation

by Hannah Proctor

Oisín Wall, The British Anti-psychiatrists: From Institutional Psychotherapy to the Counter-Culture, 1960-1971 (London: Routledge, 2018)

The Spring 1972 issue of the short-lived self-published journal Red Rat: The Journal of Abnormal Psychologists includes a review by Ruth Davies of Ken Loach’s film Family Life alongside the Yugoslavian director Dušan Makavejev’s W.R., Mysteries of the Organism.[ref]Ruth Davies, ‘Film Review: W.R. + Family Life’, Red Rat: The Journal of Abnormal Psychologists, 4, Spring 1972, pp. 28-29, p. 28. Issues of Red Rat are held in the archives at MayDay Rooms, London.[/ref] According to the reviewer both films were then showing simultaneously at the Academy Cinema on Oxford Street in London and in ‘both cases, the theme of the film is the work of a radical psychologist whose ideas have helped lay the foundations of alternative psychology; in the case of Family Life, the work of RD Laing, and in Mysteries of the Organism, Wilhelm Reich.’ Davies outlines the different approaches to psychology presented in the films: ‘Family Life is an account of the genesis of schizophrenia firmly in the Laing tradition,’ following a young woman whose diagnosis with schizophrenia is presented as deriving from her family situation, while W.R., Mysteries of the Organism combines documentary footage shot in America (interviewing people at Wilhelm Reich’s infamous Organon laboratory and following various artists around New York) with a heavily stylised narrative about sexual revolutionaries in Belgrade encountering a dashing Soviet figure skater who embodies Communism in its repressive and sexually repressed form. Though Davies is primarily concerned with the content of these two films, I was struck by how their wildly contrasting formal qualities–Loach’s drab naturalism (people wearing beige clothes drinking beige cups of tea in beige institutional rooms) versus Makavejev’s audacious experimentalism (people tearing off lurid clothes knocking down the walls of their bohemian rooms)–resembles a contrast at the heart of Oisín Wall’s new book, The British Anti-psychiatrists: From Institutional Psychotherapy to the Counter-Culture, 1960-1971. Wall demonstrates that British anti-psychiatry in the period immediately preceding the release of these films in Britain in 1971 was connected to the staid ‘square’ world of professional medicine, as well as being hugely influential within the ‘hip’ counter-culture, involving ‘collusions and collaborations between the long-haired kaftan wearing radicals who inhabit the 1960s of the contemporary popular imagination and people who, at another time, would have been the epitome of bourgeoisie [sic] stability’ (p. 2). As such, Wall’s narrative shuttles between beige institutional spaces and anarchic psychedelic communes, sees middle-aged doctors living alongside young hippies, and describes unlikely convergences of medical, spiritual, philosophical, and political discourses.

One of the most persuasive arguments Wall advances in The British Anti-Psychiatrists, and the book’s main intervention, is an insistence on the importance of acknowledging continuities and connections between the theories, practices and communities of the mainstream ‘psy’ disciplines and those of anti-psychiatry. As Wall explains, RD Laing arrived in London from Glasgow in 1956 with the intention of training as a psychoanalyst. Laing and Aaron Esterton’s work with people diagnosed with schizophrenia that forms the basis of Sanity, Madness and the Family (1964) was undertaken while Laing was involved with the Tavistock Institute of Human Relations. Laing began his analysis with Charles Rycroft, supervised by DW Winnicott and Marion Milner (prominent figures in the ‘Independent Group’ of British psychoanalysts), who were both subsequently listed in the training programme of the Philadelphia Association. Wall observes in a footnote that Winnicott invited Laing to deliver a paper at the British Psychoanalytic Association in 1966, of which Winnicott was then the president, and ‘practically begged’ Laing to join as a member (p. 181). Wall claims that even at the height of their counter-cultural notoriety when they were most vocal in their critiques of the medical establishment and of professional hierarchies, the British anti-psychiatrists continued to invoke their psychiatric credentials to gain legitimacy in certain contexts: ‘the anti-psychiatrists were not averse to using the authority of their professional status to prove a point or advance a position’ (p. 91).

A contextual chapter also places the radical therapeutic communities associated with anti-psychiatry in historical perspective, discussing their antecedents in mainstream psychiatry. Wall describes the therapeutic communities established at Northfields and Mill Hill during the Second World War and demonstrates that many principles that would go on to be central to anti-psychiatry–including an emphasis on the therapeutic benefits of group dynamics that challenged the centrality of the doctor-patient relationship–were commonplace in psychiatry by the 1950s (Wall mentions the example of a 1953 World Health Organisation report on The Community Mental Hospital, for instance). He also makes clear not only that critiques of traditional asylums were already being voiced by the time anti-psychiatry emerged but that mental hospital reform was well underway: ‘the Anti-Psychiatric movement’s antipathy to the hospital was well rooted in established psychiatric practrices and discourses’ (p. 50). Though Wall does still assert that it would be ‘naïve to suggest’ that anti-psychiatry’s ‘widespread cultural influence’ was completely unrelated to the eventual ‘deinstitutionalisation of the British asylums in the 1980s and 1990s’ (p. 8).

Although Wall challenges the novelty of the two most well-known British anti-psychiartic spaces, Villa 21 and Kingsley Hall, he nonetheless concludes that both ‘went farther’ than the therapeutic communities that preceded them ‘in the informality of staff-patient relationships, the democratic arrangement of the community and the de-stigmatization of mental illness’ (p. 78). Wall’s account of David Cooper’s experiments at Villa 21, a community established at Shenley Hospital in the early 1960s, is particularly illuminating, including perspectives from interviews conducted with two former patients, one of whom was much more cynical in his reflections than the other, indicating that the bombastic theoretical pronouncements made by British anti-psychiatrists in their best-selling published work often played out ambiguously in practice: ‘I don’t think anyone really understood why we were there or what we were trying to achieve, or what it was meant to achieve by us being there’ (p. 66).

Kingsley Hall in East London was the most infamous anti-psychiatric space, renowned for its raucous LSD-fuelled parties as much as for its innovative therapeutic methods. Wall emphasises the American psychiatrist Joe Berke’s role in providing links with the kinds of counter-cultural figures conventionally associated with the building, but he points out that visits from celebrities, artists, and hip international radical psychiatrists like Franco Basaglia and Félix Guattari were combined with those from ‘the world of ‘square’ psychiatry’ (p. 74). He also discusses tensions that emerged within the community that would have lasting implications for anti-psychiatry, particularly between Laing and Esterton; the former more anarchic and experimental, the latter more interested in retaining some conventional medical techniques and boundaries. Laing allegedly carried a Lenin book under his arm, while Esterton read Stalin.

Wall not only discusses anti-psychiatry’s psychiatric roots but also traces the ways it eventually grew entangled with the counter-culture, through a consideration of anti-psychiatrists’ links with Alexander Trocchi’s Project Sigma, their organisation of the Dialectics of Liberation Congress at the Roundhouse in London in 1967, and their involvement in establishing the Anti-University. As in other sections of the book, he highlights the forms of power still at play in these ostensibly non-hierarchical and informal networks of interpersonal relationships. Wall is at pains to show that there’s something counter-intuitive about the place these bourgeois medical professionals came to occupy among trendy young radicals, but also demonstrates how their ideas in this period of counter-cultural engagement broadened out from a critique of the psychiatric hospital to one of society at large, emphasising the numerous oppressive institutions of which society was comprised: ‘anti-psychiatry prescribed an apparently liberatory programme that demanded social, and not only psychiatric, change. This change, they argued, should be based on a fundamental reorganization of the interpersonal relations that bind society together’ (p. 79). 

Overall, The British Anti-Psychiatrists is more interested in concrete contexts than abstract concepts, in practices more than theories (or at least in how theory was practically instantiated), and the book is more interesting for that focus. The closing chapters venture into more theoretical territory, however, containing discussions of Laing’s and Cooper’s key concepts and published works. Wall briefly outlines the influence of Sartrean existentialism on Laing and Cooper; the notion that ‘madness’ can be understood as resulting from discrepancies between a person’s individual existential reality and the social reality they inhabit.[ref]Despite Wall’s introductory statements bewailing the absence of women from the British anti-psychiatry movement (p. 16), he nonetheless seems not to have reflected on the implications of using male pronouns to refer to all people in some of these later sections.[/ref] He is clear to distinguish anti-psychiatric theory from caricatures of it, asserting that certain ideas commonly associated with Laing and Cooper, particularly a romantic characterisation of madness as a form of ‘break through’, were articulated by them only rarely. He also usefully contextualises their discussions of psychic ‘liberation’ in relation to contemporaneous discourses (Third World Liberation, on the one hand, and legacies of the Second World War, on the other). The book’s final chapter on theories of the family satisfyingly loops back from the counter-culture to reiterate the book’s core argument that the anti-psychiatrists’ ‘cultural revolutionary rhetoric emerged directly out of mainstream psychiatric discourse’ (p. 143).

I found myself occasionally infuriated by the vagueness of some of the ideas presented in the book, particularly Cooper’s and Laing’s insistence on the ‘necessity of mediating between the micro-social and the macro-political’ (p. 103), but having read their speeches from the Dialectics of Liberation Congress, I’m aware that this says more about my frustrations with Laing’s and Cooper’s ideas than it does about Wall’s glosses of them, though his impeccably even-handed tone is a little unrelenting for my tastes. Reading the book I found myself longing for smatterings of archness, humour, poeticism or polemic.

Again, these objections to the style of The British Anti-Psychiatrists are not really faults it would be fair to level at Wall individually or at this book in particular, but stem from more general frustrations about the limitations implicitly imposed by established conventions of genre and discipline (which are in turn connected to the demands and expectations of academic institutions and publishers), constraints I also feel acutely aware of when I write. Yet these frustrations seem worth thinking through when the historical material being presented is politically radical, formerly inventive or critical of existing structures. I might find some of Laing’s and Cooper’s arguments less persuasive than Wall seems to, but the sweeping analyses, rhetorical bombast and literary flourishes that characterise their publications couldn’t be further from the polite timidity of tone so pervasive in current academic history writing. Unlike in the main body of the text, The British Anti-Psychiatrist’s preface–in which Wall situates his project in dialogue with political struggles today, relates it to his own political commitments and talks about first encountering Laing’s enigmatic literary work Knots (1970) as a teenager–does significantly deviate from the unofficially mandated scholarly mode, giving a glimpse of themes and concerns which guided the book’s composition but remain latent or muffled in its final form. If, as Wall claims, ‘the issues that drove the radicalism of the 1960s are still very much alive and kicking’ (p. x) and concern for these issues partially motivated him to write the book in first place, would it not be possible to write this history in such a way that made the contemporary urgency of those issues manifest?

Aside from these slightly churlish or at least tangential reservations about form and style, I would also love to have read more about the two communities that succeeded Kingsley Hall: the Archway Community and Sid’s Place, the former of which is the subject of Peter Robinson’s extraordinarily intimate 1972 documentary Asylum. Wall only mentions these spaces briefly, which makes it difficult to make full sense of his claim that they represented a ‘significant shift’ in their move away from ‘politics and counter-cultural fervour’ (p. 76). I wondered if there might not be ways to think about those experiments laterally, in relation to the flourishing of squatting and communal living experiments in London at that time, which could frame them as differently rather than simply less political. Luke Fowler’s Turner Prize nominated 2011 film All Divided Selves, though focused on Laing, gestures towards such connections through its inclusion of footage relating to squats, activist-run Day Centres and the radical group COPE (Community Organisation for Psychiatric Emergencies[ref]For a brief discussion of COPE (which underwent several name changes) see, Nick Crossley, Contesting Psychiatry: Social Movements in Mental Health (London: Routledge, 2006) pp. 172-173. [/ref]). This lingering question links to a reservation I had with Wall’s conclusion that by the early 1970s (when Laing went off to meditate in Ceylon and Cooper sought out militancy in Argentina) anti-psychiatric ideas had lost their significance (p. 177). Although in his introduction he claims that anti-psychiatry ‘paved the way for the birth of the Service User’s Movement’ (p. 8), I would make a stronger case than this book does that the trenchant critiques of mainstream psychiatric diagnoses and treatments articulated by people active in the Women’s Liberation Movement and Gay Liberation Movement and the proliferation of self-organised non-professional therapy groups, not to mention the emergence of the psychiatric survivors movement and radical groups of psychiatrists critical of the medical establishment (like those involved with the journal Red Rat), indicate the influence and extension of anti-psychiatric ideas well into the 1970s. While I think Wall is right to insist on the specificities of the British anti-psychiatrists’ approach, contra much of the existing scholarship on anti-psychiatry which often places them alongside contemporaneous American, French, German or Italian figures and movements (p. 21), there is also something about the extent of the British anti-psychiatrists’ fame and the wide and diffuse percolation of their ideas that undermines this approach, as Wall notes: ‘it is impossible to quantify the influence’ (p. 8).

One of Peter Sedgwick’s main intentions in his anti-anti-psychiatry diatribe Psycho Politics (1982) was to distinguish Laing’s actual theories and practices from caricatured versions of them in popular circulation (his ire was often not primarily directed at Laing himself but at those on the left who mistook Laing for a Marxist), but I would contend that caricatured, over-simplified, wishfully politicised or deliberately partial readings of Laing’s work also form part of the history and legacy of anti-psychiatry in Britain.[ref]I wrote about Peter Sedgwick’s work on Laing at length here: https://www.radicalphilosophy.com/article/lost-minds. [/ref] Sedgwick may not have approved either way, but Laing’s work inspired activists regardless of Laing’s own political evasiveness and increasing spiritualism. The fact that some people may have misread Laing or chosen to discard aspects of his work does little to undermine the things they were inspired to do as a result. The unquantifiable influence of anti-psychiatry that Wall identifies also had a historical reality, which, though its elusiveness by definition poses difficulties for the historian, it nonetheless seems worth attempting to capture.

The archival material of TV interviews and documentaries in Luke Fowler’s All Divided Selves is interspersed with 16mm footage shot by the filmmaker – a glimpse of blue sky streaked with clouds, long grass in sunlight brushing against a wire fence, sheep grazing placidly in a bracken-filled field, murky landscapes seemingly shot at dusk. The connection of these images to the film’s content is oblique, but their presence participates in conjuring an atmosphere that seems appropriate to the psychic states anti-psychiatry explored, just as in W.R., Mysteries of the Organism the orangey kaleidoscopic opening shots of sexual abandon helped convey the Reichian pronouncements that accompany them through a voiceover. Historians are not artists and Laing’s Sonnets (1979) serve as a reminder that venturing beyond one’s discipline to embrace formal experimentation might not always be a particularly good idea, but perhaps historians of radicalism interested in producing radical modes of history writing appropriate to their subjects can still learn something from other genres or media when thinking about how to present radical pasts in ways that might challenge or inspire people in the oppressive present.


Hannah Proctor is a postdoctoral fellow affiliated with the ICI Berlin. She’s in the process of finishing her first monograph Psychologies in Revolution: Alexander Luria, Soviet Subjectivities and Cultural History and is embarking on a second book project on the psychic aftermaths of left-wing political movements. She is a member of the editorial collective of Radical Philosophy.

Psychotherapy across the Atlantic

The new special issue of History of the Human Sciences, edited by Sarah Marks, focuses on psychotherapy in Europe. Articles range across the twentieth century, tracing psychoanalysis in Greece, the transnational shaping of Yugoslav psychotherapy, hypnosis in Hungary, the role of suggestion in Soviet medicine, mindfulness in Britain, and Dialectical Behaviour Therapy in Sweden. In parallel, History of Psychology have published a special issue on psychotherapy in the Americas, edited by Rachael Rosner. Here, Marks and Rosner discuss the authors’ contributions, and what’s at stake when writing about the history of psychotherapy.

Sarah Marks (SM): Perhaps we can start by tracing how the idea for these issues came about. You and I first met at a conference at University College London in 2013 organised by myself and Sonu Shamdasani on the history of psychotherapy – but the idea for these parallel issues came from you: what was the motivation behind the idea, and the particular focus of Europe and the Americas?

Rachael Rosner (RR): Your conference was a watershed moment for me personally. For years I had been trying to figure out where the history of psychotherapy belonged. The history of science? The history of medicine? The history of the social, behavioral and human sciences? Psychotherapy straddles all of them, but from the standpoint of historians asking shared questions, there wasn’t yet a home base. Your conference was an important step in that direction.

Rachael Rosner

Sonu followed in 2016 with a mini think-tank on transcultural histories of psychotherapy, which you and I attended. Felicity Callard (who had been at the 2013 conference) had just assumed co-editorship of History of the Human Sciences and Nadine Weidman had just become editor of History of Psychology. It seemed like Felicity and Nadine would likely encourage good work coming out of this nascent community. So the idea just clicked that you and I might guest-edit coordinated issues as a way of continuing the momentum. The idea was inspired by a strategy National Institutes of Health researchers had used in the late 1960s to nurture psychotherapy researchers. They published the proceedings of a workshops on psychotherapy research methods in two journals simultaneously, American Psychologist and Archives of General Psychiatry. I thought we might try something similar. Thankfully, you, Nadine and Felicity were enthusiastic. Your expertise was in European psychotherapy and mine in American, so we would focus on those regions. But this was just a starting point. Excellent work is being done on the history of psychotherapy in Asia and India and, hopefully soon also, in Africa.

SM: Both of these issues try to put the question of place at the centre of the debate – both in terms of local specificities, and the transfer of knowledge and practice across borders and cultures. For Europe, it’s curious how much long-term continuity there was despite the geopolitical divisions of the Cold War – practices including hypnosis, suggestion and group psychoanalysis which emerged in Western and Central Europe in the earlier half of the century remained in play in different parts of Eastern Europe well into the 1960s and 1970s. And we also see the crucial importance of transatlantic connections in both directions, especially from America to Europe in recent years. How did transnational and transcultural stories play out within the Americas?

RR: What is astonishing is how many of the innovations in the Americas were local improvisations on European trends. It’s not surprising that this transfer of knowledge happened within psychoanalysis, but our special issue illustrates that it was happening in other domains too. In Argentina, as Alejandro Dagfal shows, French ideas consistently spurred psychotherapeutic innovations. Jennifer Lambe’s and Cristiana Facchinetti’s and Alexander Jabert’s pieces also show the French influence, in this case among followers of French spiritualist Alan Kardec (Kardecian Spiritists). Erica Dyck’s and Patrick Farrell’s paper on LSD therapy tells the story of a disaffected British psychiatrist who found support in the isolation of the Canadian prairies. In America the trans-Atlantic trends were more heterogenous and reciprocal. British psychotherapists played a huge role in catapulting American Aaron Beck to stardom, just as Beck’s CBT helped British clinicians gain advantage with the NHS. The only article in our special issue that doesn’t follow the transcultural theme is Deborah Weinstein’s account of how family therapists in America embraced the removal of homosexuality from the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorder (DSM-III) and came to normalize both homosexuality and gay families.

SM: We know that many forms of psychotherapeutic have long been entangled with religious or spiritual practices, right back to the Quaker Tuke family at the York Retreat in the 1890s – and Matthew Drage shows in HHS that Buddhism has remained a significant driving force in the transmission of mindfulness practice in Britain, even as it has become bound up with cognitive science and evidence-based outcomes studies in recent years. It seems that religion played an even more central role in psychotherapy – albeit in slightly different ways – in North and South America in the 20th Century. Could you tell us more about what your authors found in relation to this?

RR: Yes, you’re right. Psychotherapies in the Americas tapped deeply into spiritual trends right from the beginning.David Schmit’s biography of Warren Felt Evans, founder of the Mind Cure movement, takes the story of religion and psychotherapy in America farther back even than Eric Caplan’s work. Americans continued to embrace the religious aspect, even if they didn’t always recognize it as such. Carl Rogers was a minister before he became a psychologist, for instance, and client-centered therapy was as much an expression of religious as psychological imperatives; immigrant psychoanalysts who made such a big mark on American psychotherapy, like Erich Fromm, Erik Erikson and Victor Frankl, were also fully engaged with religious questions. When D. T. Suzuki brought his Buddhist practices to America mid-century, Erich Fromm and behavior therapist Albert J. (Mickey) Stunkard were hugely enthusiastic. These are just some examples of how the religious impulse remained strong throughout the history of American psychotherapy. We might imagine that Catholicism would come into play, especially in Central and South American psychotherapies, and there is scholarship to suggest as much. But the big surprise in our special issue was Kardecian Spiritism in Cuba and Brazil. Kardecian Spiritism had no presence at all in North America. So this is an exciting line of research.  

Sarah V. Marks

SM: You yourself have done considerable work on the history of Cognitive Behavioural Therapy (CBT) in America, especially in relation to the work of Aaron Beck. Could you tell us a bit more about how you have started to write this in to the broader history of psychotherapy?

RR: Beck’s Cognitive Therapy (CT) can be difficult to grasp from the standpoint of the history of the human sciences because there is little in it that speaks to the subjective or the emotional—his ideas don’t intersect with art, literature, philosophy, the linguistic turn, etc. This lack of intersection, however, is also what makes Beck’s CT interesting historically. CT flourished at the turn of the 21st century in the U.S. and the U.K. precisely because of tensions between objectivity and subjectivity. Most psychoanalysts by then were plunging even deeper into the subjective, under the influence of Lacan, Foucault, and others. But the vast majority of non-analytic therapists—largely psychologists and social workers—were making a mad dash in the opposite direction, to objectivity. The rise of the Randomised Control Trial meant that therapists seeking federal research funding or reimbursement for treatment had no choice but to embrace objectivity. Beck was in the right place at the right time. He had been plying CT since the early 1960, with only moderate success. But now, suddenly, by 1985 or so, CT and CBT were the gold standard. They met the clinical, economic and research needs of a large number of therapists. Interestingly, the supremacy of the objective didn’t mean that Beck’s followers abdicated the subjective. They have rather been engaged in a subtle dance between objectivity and subjectivity that is fascinating to study historically.

SM: I’m aware that you’re writing a biography at the moment – could you say a bit about the challenges and rewards of biography as a genre?

RR: Historians of science often malign biography as soft scholarship. Mike Sokal has done a good job challenging this assumption, but there’s more work to do. One of the major challenges of writing biography is convincing historians that the argument is not parochial or hagiographical. That’s a tall order. I believe that biography is uniquely well-suited to the history of psychotherapy. Psychotherapy actually defies the categories historians use for bracketing our subject matter. I do not believe that psychotherapy is in fact a sub-genre of medicine, or science, the behavioral sciences, religion, psychology, or anything else. No profession has managed to corner the market on its practice. Psychotherapy is, rather, a historical chameleon. Maybe “shape shifter” is a more accurate description. Psychotherapy quickly assumes the characteristics, colors, virtues and temperament of the person practicing it—whether that person is a doctor, a minister, a rabbi, a mystic, a housewife, a psychologist or a brush salesman. Each iteration is unique to the practitioner. Biography taps into that idiographic quality. We can write social, cultural, intellectual, and other kinds of histories of psychotherapy, and they are all worthwhile. But biographies get to the core of psychotherapy because they get to the core of the person who is practicing it. Several years ago I attended the annual conference of BIO (Biographer’s International Organization), and the keynote speaker remarked that what she loves about biography is that it  is experience in our shared humanity. Biographers are trying to make emotional contact, to have a shared experience, with their subjects. I love that.

SM: Like a number of my colleagues, you write from the perspective of the humanities and historical research, but you also have a background in the clinical world, and you believe strongly in the importance of writing for an audience of practitioners. Could you tell us a bit more about why this is important, and what is at stake when writing histories for this readership?

RR: I became a historian, in part, in order to agitate clinicians. The back-story is that my father was a clinical psychologist who had trained at the University of Chicago in the 1960s with people like Roy Grinker, Jr. and Bruno Bettelheim. Carl Rogers had just left Chicago, but his influence there was still very strong. Our home library included books by Freud, Jung, Fromm, Bettllheim, Rogers and others, all of whom I read avidly. I had intended to become a clinical psychologist like my father, but it became clear during my training that I was not cut out for clinical practice. Clinicians were making all kinds of assumptions about human nature I wasn’t prepared to make. They were being trained to solve problems, not to think critically, but thinking critically seemed to be where I lived. I’d been in search of a mechanism through which to bring that kind of critical inquiry to the community of clinicians about whom I cared so much. The History and Theory Area in the Department of Psychology at York University (Toronto), where I did my Ph.D. under Dr. Raymond Fancher, offered that kind of mechanism. History as practiced there was all about engaging psychologists in difficult conversations about what they do and why.

Psychotherapists fill a unique niche in western society. They are tasked with the care of emotional lives when those lives have become rocky and troubled. Neither the government nor medicine nor the church is particularly good at meeting this need, so this is a crucial function. Every therapist I have ever met, including my father, believed that theirs is a noble calling. They rarely, if ever, question the intrinsic and self-evident goodness of what they do. But to my mind it’s crucial that they do just that—or run the risk of doing harm. Sadly, I know too many stories where therapists’ over-confidence made matters worse for a patient, not better. This is a situation ripe for historical agitation, for inviting therapists to ask hard questions and, in the process, to take a more circumspect and thoughtful stance in their work.

Rachael Rosner works as an independent scholar. Her most recent articles include ‘Manualizing psychotherapy: Aaron T. Beck and the origins of Cognitive Therapy of Depression’ in The European Journal of Counselling and Psychotherapy, and ‘The Splendid Isolation of Aaron T. Beck” in Isis.

Sarah Marks is a postdoctoral researcher at Birkbeck, University of London and Reviews Editor for History of the Human Sciences. She writes on the psy-disciplines during the Cold War, and currently works with the Wellcome-funded Hidden Persuaders project.

Deafness, Sovietness

by Anaïs Van Ertvelde

Claire L. Shaw. Deaf in the USSR: Marginality, Community and Soviet Identity, 1917-1991; Ithaca: Cornell University Press; 310 pages; hardback $49.95; ISBN: 1501713663

In a picture taken during the 1933 May Day Parade in Moscow, we witness a procession of young athletes with firm bodies walking towards the Red Square. Dressed in a uniform of sporty blouses and practical shorts, the athletes are on their way to the Lenin Mausoleum, where they can salute the USSR’s top leaders. It’s a display seen a hundred times over – one that historians in training study in a first year course, or the general public has seen in any given documentary on life in the USSR. It would be a wholly unremarkable picture, if it were not for one detail. The first column of male and female athletes carries a banner which reads ‘glukhonemye’ or ‘deaf-mutes’. ‘With their cheerful appearance, the deaf-mutes testified to their readiness to fight alongside the working class of the USSR for the general line of the party and its leader, comrade Stalin’ the then magazine for deaf-mutes Zhizn glukhonemykh wrote about the event. Deaf people seemed intent on participating in Soviet life. They dedicated themselves to overcoming the obstacles to their inclusion into the Soviet project in general and the industrial workforce in particular. For it was the Soviet project, many leading figures in the burgeoning deaf community felt, that gave them the opportunities to emancipate themselves. No longer were they the dependent, disabled people they had been under the tsarist regime – now they could become valuable members of the working class.

Lenin’s Mausoleum. Attribution: R. Seiben, via Wikimedia Commons. CC-BY-SA-3.0 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/

However much the deaf athletes, or the editors of Zhizn glukhonemykh, subscribed to a narrative of radical inclusion, or framed perfecting the deaf masses as a Soviet aim pur sang, they were also confronted with exclusion. In everyday life not everyone was equally capable of realizing the utopian rhetoric of overcoming deafness. The deaf people on the May Day Parade picture marched alongside their hearing comrades but also distinguished themselves by carrying a banner proclaiming their deaf-muteness. This was illustrative of the separate institutions that helped deaf soviet citizens develop a distinguished communal identity, but also at times kept them at a substantial distance from the hearing world.

It is precisely these kinds of tensions between the deaf identity project and the Soviet identity project, between inclusion and exclusion, sameness and difference, which lies at the heart of Claire Shaw’s Deaf in the USSR: Marginality, Community and Soviet Identity. Shaw writes a history of deafness in the USSR from the February Revolution of 1917, to the collapse of the USSR in 1991, while situating deafness in the broader programme of Soviet selfhood. She examines the different Soviet conceptions of deafness throughout the period as influenced by factors ranging from self-advocacy, science, defectology, schooling and technology; to institutionalization, ideology and professionalization. To this end, Shaw draws on deaf journalism, films and literature produced by deaf and hearing people alike, as well as personal memoires. The main body of her source material hails from the institutional archive of VOG, an acronym that covered the different names that the Russian Society of the Deaf bore throughout the period under scrutiny. According to Shaw, VOG offers a lens through which we can gain an understanding of what it meant to be deaf that is both broad and in-depth. The society was involved with activities concerning housing, education, sign language, literacy, labour placement, cultural work, and social services, and was, as Shaw notes early on, a locus for ‘both Soviet governance and grassroots activism and community building.’ By the end of the 19070s it was estimated that more than 98% of Russian deaf people were members of VOG, although the core of its operations were directed from Moscow and to a lesser extent St. Petersburg. Inevitably, and with some exceptions, much of Shaw’s focus is on these cities.

The first chapter traces the foundation of VOG in 1926 after a period of reconceptualising deafness in reaction to the tsarist period and in exchange with the new Soviet ideas. Deaf people drew upon models developed by  women and ethnic minorities to turn their differences into a path towards Sovietness while simultaneously insisting that ‘the affairs of the deaf-mutes are their own.’ Chapter two brings us to the 1930s when VOG becomes an organization of mass politics and deaf people try to write themselves into the Stalinist transformative narrative. At the same time, fears about those deaf people who could not live up to the ideal spread within the deaf organization. Chapter three examines the break in deaf history that was the Great Patriotic War. Disabled war veterans raised the overall status of people with disabilities and the postwar state infrastructure was rebuilt with an emphasis on welfare. Both trends rendered VOG a stronger and more centrally controlled organization. They also raised the existing tensions in the deaf community between striving for autonomy and being ‘passive’ recipients of expertise and care services. Chapter four zooms in on the Golden Age of deafness during the 1950s and 1960s in which deaf cultural institutions and educational efforts flourished. Deaf people came close to a functional hybrid deaf/Soviet identity that was also advertised to the world at large. Chapter five takes a detour to follow up on a nationwide debate about deaf criminality and lingering fears concerning deafness, femaleness, marginality, and otherness., while chapter six tracks the downfall of the deaf cultural community in the Brzehnev era: deaf models of selfhood gave way to curative and technological visions. Finally, an epilogue outlines with broad strokes the evolutions deafness underwent after the collapse of Soviet Union.

Deaf in the USSR is often at its most compelling when it grapples with the category of deafness itself. Many of our conceptions of what disability and deafness actually are have roots in 20th century disability and Deaf activism, and scholarship from the UK and the US. These conceptions bear specific political and historical connotations that are not self-evidently transferable to the context of Soviet Russia. Proponents of global disability studies have been rewriting this Anglo-American conceptual framework of disability to suit local contexts for quite some time now, but what place the former ‘Soviet world’ is to be assigned within global disability studies is still quite unclear. Few authors have tried their hand at the endeavour (See, for instance, the work of Michael Rembis & Natalia Pamuła [in Polish]).

Shaw employs her national case study to elaborate on specific Soviet understandings of deafness. A social interpretation of deafness, for example, was prevalent in the USSR decades before disability activists in the UK and the US formulated the social model of disability. Moreover, Shaw does so without falling into the trap of completely disconnecting the history of the USSR from international developments. After all, the social model of disability, as developed in the UK in the 1970s, was inspired by Marxism, while early Soviet conceptions of deafness in turn were influenced by 19th century conceptions of deafness hailing from German and French deaf education.

Dr Claire Shaw, author of ‘Deaf in the USSR.’

‘Could a defective body ever embody the Soviet ideal?’ is the question that returns throughout Deaf in the USSR. It is used by Shaw as a window onto the moulding of the Soviet self and, more importantly, onto the limitations of this moulding. While Shaw sporadically touches upon the subject of how deafness was related to other defective bodies, the topic is never fully addressed. Shaw emphasizes how work and employment were essential to overcoming deafness and approaching the Soviet ideal. In this regard deafness distinguishes itself from other disabilities, as it does not make access to physical labour quite as difficult. A limited discussion of the relation between ‘Soviet’ deafness and other forms of ‘Soviet’ disability would not have been uncalled for, especially as Shaw seems to take issue with the dire picture of disability in the USSR painted by researchers such as Michael Rasell and Elena Iarskaia-Smirnova.

Shaw is clearly interested in how studying deafness in the USSR can shed light on more than the history of deafness itself. At several points throughout the book she demonstrates that deafness can be useful for reevaluating broader historiographical debates. In the case of the 1933 May Day Parade photograph, she asserts that such forms of deaf inclusion shed a new light on this period. The 1930s have often been depicted as a decade in which earlier, more plural socialist visions of equality and emancipation where completely buried by the dictatorial regime of Stalin. Shaw’s broader reflections could have been worked through in more depth, but they show an important willingness to leave behind the type of disability history that follows an ‘add disability and stir’ recipe. It is in these attempts that the reader sometimes catches a glimpse of the full potential of disability as a as category of historical analysis: valuable both in its own right, and in its ability to pinpoint questions about a society at large.

Anaïs Van Ertvelde is a PhD student at the Leiden University Institute for History on the ERC funded project Rethinking Disability: The Global Impact of the International Year of Disabled Persons (1981) in Historical Perspective. Her current research focuses on how government experts, disability movements and people with disabilities themselves conceive of, and deal with, disability in the wake of the UN international year. She uses a cross-‘iron curtain’ perspective that involves three local case studies and their global entanglements: Belgium, Poland, and Canada.

Between discomfort and trauma

Emily J.M. Knox (ed.). Trigger Warnings: History, Theory, Context; London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2017; 298 pages; hardback £54.95; ISBN 978-1-4422-7371-9 .

by Sarah Chaney

In August 2016, the University of Chicago sent a letter to new students that received a great deal of academic and media interest. In the letter John “Jay” Ellison, Dean of Students, stated that the university was committed to “intellectual freedom”, indicating that other concepts referred to – “safe spaces” and “trigger warnings” among them – were antithetical to this notion. The connection between these concepts, as well as the letter itself, was much debated at the time, and the issues raised appear to be the starting point for many of the essays in this book. Are students’ minds really being coddled, or are there valuable things to be learnt from the use of trigger warnings and the debate surrounding them?

Trigger Warnings: History, Theory, Context does not take a clear-cut and dogmatic approach to the topic (as some others have done, most prominently those who object outright to the idea of trigger warnings like Greg Lukianoff and Jonathan Haidt). Most authors in this volume adopt a carefully critical view of trigger warnings that also seeks to understand and explore their implications and uses. The book focuses on higher education in North America; the location is only to be expected, perhaps, as this is where the bulk of debate has taken place. A few essays do look beyond higher education to the broader context from which trigger warnings emerged, including a rather Whiggish history of trigger warnings based on retrospective diagnosis of Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder (chapter 1) and a more incisive look at the use of trigger warnings in the treatment of eating disorders since the 1970s (chapter 3).

The volume claims to be interdisciplinary, although contributions largely stem from those working in the arts, humanities and social sciences. This is understandable: these fields have probably been the most affected by calls for trigger warnings, as well as being concerned with the practice of critical thinking and debate (which, according to their detractors, trigger warnings stifle). The inclusion of a number of authors with a background in library and information studies raises an interesting angle for historians about the way collections are labelled and configured. As Emily Knox indicates in the introduction, the American Library Association has long been opposed to the rating of texts, a practice which holds political connotations and has tended to be fairly arbitrary, usually based on the attitudes of a small group of people. Despite voicing this opposition, however, Knox goes on to raise the central tenet that runs throughout this book: while trigger warnings can and may be used as a form of censorship, teachers and lecturers also have an obligation to consider the welfare of their students.

These two potentially conflicting ideas are reflected in the division of the book into two parts. Starting with the context and theory around trigger warnings, the second half moves on to specific case studies, designed to try and offer some practical guidance for teachers. While Kari Storla does this excellently in her piece on handling traumatic topics in classroom discussion, other case studies are less satisfying and the first half of the book is ultimately of more interest to the historian, grappling as it does with the controversies raised by trigger warnings and placing them in wider context. Are warnings important for welfare, or damaging to students’ critical thinking? Do they protect or censor? Do they fulfil a genuine need for students or do universities use them to avoid confronting systemic issues around student welfare? Most authors do not resolve these questions – indeed, few come down squarely on one side or the other. This in itself reflects the complexity of the debate. It is, of course, possible in each case cited above for both things to be true, even in the same example.

Take Stephanie Houston Grey’s chapter on the history of warnings around eating disorders. This is one of the most thought-provoking and well-written articles in the book. Grey explores the public health response to eating disorders in the late 1970s, which she argues was one of the first instances in which widespread efforts were made to restrict speech on the grounds of preventing contagion. This “moral panic” resulted in crackdowns on eating-disordered individuals, most prominently online, which stripped basic civil rights from people but was nonetheless unsuccessful in reducing the prevalence of eating disorders. Grey’s thoughtful examination of one specific example that began nearly thirty years before trigger warnings became widespread online is an interesting opportunity for reflection on the emergence of triggers. In the case of eating disorders, labelling images and words as triggering might have begun from concerns about people’s welfare, but ultimately became repressive and silencing of people with eating disorders. Providing “critical thinking tools and skill sets”, Grey suggests, might instead assist people to engage in more productive conversations around eating disorders.

Although the context of public concern about contagion is very different from the modern emphasis on managing individual trauma, there are certain lines of similarity with other pieces in the book. Indeed, an emphasis on critical thinking tools to aid welfare is one of the most practical suggestions that emerges from the volume as a whole. As Storla notes, one of the biggest myths around the use of trigger warnings is the assumption that a blanket warning alone can somehow prevent students from experiencing trauma. Storla’s “trauma-informed pedagogy” instead provides a nuanced framework which incorporates student participation at every turn. Her classes develop their own guidelines, debate the use of warnings at the start of the course and consider the difference between discomfort and trauma. This provides a lesson to students in considering multiple viewpoints (in particular those of the rest of the class). Similarly, in their chapter Kristina Ruiz-Mesa, Julie Matos and Gregory Langner suggest that encouraging students to consider the differing backgrounds of their audiences can be a valuable lesson in public speaking. In both cases, trigger warnings become part of the educational content rather than being in opposition to it.

Trigger warnings can, then, be about opening up conversation as well as closing it down. Several authors, including Jane Gavin-Herbert and Bonnie Washick, suggest that student demands for trigger warnings may not even necessarily be about individual experiences of trauma but based in wider concerns about structural violence and inequality. Taking seriously and discussing these concerns may have more impact than a simplistic warning. Indeed, Storla argues that one of her techniques – the use of “safe words” by which students can bring an end to class discussion without having to give a personal reason for doing so – has never been used by a student in her classroom. However, its existence as part of a set of communal guidelines, she feels, means students are safe and supported and thus able to engage more fully in debates. Paradoxically, having the opportunity to censor discussion might actually promote it.

As a general guide, most of the authors in this volume agree that trigger warnings are an ethical and legal practice that can and should be put in place as part of increasing access to higher education. The people most likely to request trigger warnings are minority groups, who are also at greatest risk of experiencing trauma. The problem, however, comes when these issues are individualised, as neoliberal interpretations of trigger warnings have tended to do. Bonnie Washick’s sympathetic critique of the equal access argument for trigger warnings raises the way in which warnings have led to the expectation that individuals who might be “triggered” are viewed as responsible for managing their own reactions. While trigger warnings might have begun as a form of activism and social protest, they have since been medicalised (through the framework of Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder) and individualised. By taking a critical and contextual approach to trigger warnings, both teachers and students can gain from discussing them.

Trigger Warnings: History, Theory and Context is a valuable contribution to the debate around trigger warnings in higher education today, as well as an interesting exploration into some of the nuances around why and how such a concept has emerged. An edited volume particularly suits the topic, allowing for multiple and varied perspectives. No reader will agree with everything they read here, but then that’s precisely the point. If, collectively, the authors in this book achieve any one thing it is to persuade this reader at least that trigger warnings have the potential to generate more insightful debate and critical thought than they risk preventing.

Sarah Chaney is a Research Fellow at Queen Mary Centre for the History of the Emotions, on the Wellcome Trust funded ‘Living With Feeling’ project. Her current research focuses on the history of compassion in healthcare, from the late nineteenth century to the present day. Her previous research has been in the history of psychiatry, in particular the topic of self-inflicted injury. Her first monograph, Psyche on the Skin: A History of Self-Harm was published by Reaktion in February 2017.

Skin, muscle, bone, brain, fluid

Jennifer Wallis, Investigating the Body in the Victorian Asylum. Doctors, Patients, and Practices, (Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan, 2017); xvi, 276 pages; 9 b/w illustrations; hardback £20.00; ISBN, 978-3-319-56713-6.

by Louise Hide

Skin, muscle, bone, brain, fluid – Jennifer Wallis has given each its own chapter in this exemplary mesh of medical, psychiatric and social history that spans work carried out in the latter decades of the nineteenth century in Yorkshire’s West Riding Pauper Lunatic Asylum. The body – usually the dead body – is at the centre of the book, playing an active role in the construction of knowledge and the evolution of practices and technologies in the physical space of the pathology lab, as well as in the emerging disciplines of the mental sciences, neurology and pathology. Wallis explores how, in the desperate quest to uncover aetiologies and treatments for mental disorders, there was a growing conviction that ‘the truth of any disease lay deep within the fabric of the body’ (Kindle: 3822). General paralysis of the insane (GPI) is central to the book. A manifestation of tertiary syphilis and a common cause of death in male asylum patients, it was one of the few conditions that produced identifiable lesions in the brain, raising hopes that the post-mortem examination could yield new discoveries around the organic origins of other mental diseases. Investigating the Body in the Victorian Asylum is, therefore, not only about how the body of the asylum patient was framed by changing socio-medical theories and practices, but about how it was productive of them too.

Whilst reading this lucidly written monograph, it soon becomes clear that West Riding was no asylum back-water. Its superintendent, James Crichton-Browne, was determined to forge a reputation in scientific research and West Riding became the first British asylum to appoint its own pathologist in 1872. Wallis has not only marshalled a vast amount of secondary literature, but made a deep and far-reaching foray into the West Riding archives, analysing some 2,000 case records of patients who died there between 1880 and 1900. Drawing on case books, post-mortem reports, administrative records and photographs, Wallis has created a refreshingly original way of conceptualising the asylum patient. Rather than exploring his – as it usually was in ‘cases’ of general paralysis – role within tangled networks of external social agencies and medical practices, she turns her focus to the inner unchartered terrain of unclaimed corpses. She shows how the autopsy provided different ways of ‘seeing’ as the interior of the body was ‘surfaced’ through a range of new and evolving practices and technologies, such as microscopy and clinical photography.  Processes for preserving human tissue and conducting post-mortem examinations were enhanced, as were methods for observing and testing tissue samples, and for recording findings. None of these practices was without an ethical dimension, such as a patient’s right to privacy and anonymity.

Doctors, perhaps, gleaned most from the living as they examined and observed patients on admission and in the wards; pathologists could venture into the deep tissues of the body, which were out of bounds for as long as a patient remained alive. Yet the two states could not be separated quite so neatly and Wallis turns her attention to the growing tensions between pathologists and asylum doctors as both scrambled to plant their disciplinary stake in the ground, navigating boundaries between the living and the dead body. How, I wondered, were practices mirrored at the London County Council pathology lab, which opened at Claybury in 1893 and also investigated various forms of tertiary syphilis, including GPI and tabes dorsalis, as well as alcoholism and tuberculosis? Wallis does touch on other laboratories, but it would be interesting to know a little more about how they associated with each other.

One of the many strengths of the book is the way in which Wallis makes connections between social and cultural mores and the impact of wider political and medical developments. Germ theory was, of course, highly influential. Wallis touches on the ‘pollution’ metaphor but might have expanded on the trope of the ‘syphilitic’ individual as a vector of moral depravity in the western context – an unexpected swerve of narrative into the belief systems of the Nuer jars slightly. Otherwise, Wallis provides a fascinating investigation of the social framing of the male body with GPI, explaining how atrophied muscle and degenerating organs might be interpreted as an assault on masculinity in a period of high industrialisation. Soft bones could be equated to a loss of virility and femininity; broken bones forced asylums to ask whether they might be due to the actions of brutal attendants, rough methods of restraint, or of physical degeneration in the patient.

Investigating the Body in the Victorian Asylum provides a meticulously researched and thoroughly readable – for all – social history of an important development in the mental sciences in the nineteenth century, centring it around the evolving practices of post-mortem examinations. I particularly like the way in which Wallis writes herself, her research process and her thinking into the book. Her respectful treatment not only of the asylum patients but of the medical and nursing staff who cared for and treated them is threaded through from beginning to end. One might not expect to be gripped by descriptions of ‘fatty muscles’, ‘boggy brains’ and ‘flabby livers’, but Wallis reveals a fascinating story that is full of originality and tells us as much about nineteenth century medical practice as about the patient himself.

Louise Hide is a Wellcome Trust Fellow in Medical Humanities and based in the Department of History, Classics and Archaeology at Birkbeck, University of London. Her research project is titled ‘Cultures of Harm in Residential Institutions for Long-term Adult Care, Britain 1945-1980s’. Her monograph Gender and Class in English Asylums, 1890-1914 was published in 2014.

 

The evolution of Raymond Aron: biological thought and the philosophy of history

In the current issue of HHS, Isabel Gabel, from the University of Chicago, analyses the links between evolutionary thought and the philosophy of history in France – showing how, in the work of Raymond Aron in particular, a moment of epistemic crisis in evolutionary theory was crucial to the formation of his thought. Here, Isabel speaks to Chris Renwick about these unexpected links between evolutionary biology and he philosophy of history. The full article is available here.

Chris Renwick (CR):Isabel,we should start with an obvious question: Raymond Aron, the main focus for your article, is a thinker most readers of History of the Human Sciences will be familiar with. But few – and I count myself among them – will have put Aron in the context you have done. What led you to connect Aron and evolutionary biology together?  

Isabel Gabel (IG): Yes, this was a real revelation for me too. I knew Aron as a sociologist, public intellectual, and Cold War liberal, but had never seen his early interest in biology mentioned anywhere. It was actually in the archives of Georges Canguilhem, at the CAPHÉS in Paris, that I stumbled upon a reference to Aron and Mendelian genetics.  In 1988 there was a colloquium organized in Aron’s honor, and Canguilhem’s remarks on Aron’s earliest years, and the problem of the philosophy of history in the 1930s, had been collected and published along with several others in a small volume. At the time, Canguilhem felt that not enough importance had been given to the fact that his late friend had abandoned a research project on Mendelian biology, as he put it. This totally surprised and, needless to say, delighted me.  I quickly found a copy of Introduction to the Philosophy of History, and began reading.

As someone who works in both history of science and intellectual history, I frame my research questions to address both fields. Aron’s development as a thinker is really a perfect illustration of how these two fields converge, because his encounter with biology can be so precisely localized in time and space. It wasn’t just that he made the obvious connection between theories of evolution and philosophical approaches to history. Rather, it was the very specific moment in which he happened to encounter evolutionary theory, and that this happened in a very French context, which so profoundly shaped his thought.

CR: An important part of your article involves outlining the context of French debates about evolution, which provides the backdrop for Aron’s early intellectual development. As a historian of evolutionary thought myself, I found this part fascinating and something I had only really encountered periodically in my research – Naomi Beck’s work on Herbert Spencer’s reception in France is one example of where I have read about these kinds of issues before. The French context seems strikingly different from the Anglophone one. What do you think the Francophone context brings to our discussions of both the history of evolutionary thought and the human science that’s related to it? 

IG: The French context is absolutely central to this story. Everything from the specifics of the French education system, to the cultural politics of Darwinism in France, to the state of the French left in the twenties and thirties played a role in how and why Aron brought evolutionary theory and the philosophy of history together. First, because debates about evolutionary mechanisms were, if not insulated from Anglophone science, at least somewhat resistant to the incursion of external concepts, the epistemic crisis of neo-Lamarckism could only have happened in France. Also, while it’s important to note that Aron’s self-understanding was very post-Henri Bergson, there is no denying Bergson’s influence on early-twentieth-century French biology. All of which is to say that mid-century France is a fascinating case for understanding the feedback loop between biology and philosophy.

Moreover, it’s the very specificity of the French case that makes it so useful for thinking through methodological questions such as the one you raise about the shared history of evolutionary thought and the human sciences. In recent years, there has been renewed interest in bringing science and humanities/social science into dialogue with one another, an impulse that historians of science should of course welcome. Part of what the story of Aron and the philosophy of history in mid-century France can teach us is how contingent these influences can be. In other words, as evolutionary theory evolves over time, so too do the ways we interpret its meaning for the human past. In France in the twenties and thirties, it was the limits of science that were most instructive to Aron. French biologists couldn’t quite bridge between observations and experiments in the present, and the theory of evolution they believed explained past events. Objectivity became, for Aron, partly about acknowledging the limits of both positivism and philosophical idealism, i.e. a way of negotiating the relationship between the limits of observation and the limits of theory.

The French context therefore instructs us not to buy in too quickly to the idea that science offers facts and humanities subsequently layer on interpretation. This picture does a disservice to both the science and the humanities. What becomes visible in the case of Aron and French evolutionary theory is that biology and philosophy were encountering parallel epistemic crises, and therefore that neither one could singlehandedly save or authorize the other.

CR: Another issue that I thought was important in connection with Raymond Aron is liberalism. As you explain in your article, most people think of liberalism when they think of Aron. However, we don’t necessarily think of liberalism when we think about evolutionary biology. Liberalism and evolutionary biology have such a fascinating and entangled history. Why do you think we are now so surprised to find people like Aron were so interested in it? 

IG: Those who know Aron by reputation as a Cold War liberal may be surprised, because the conversations he helped shape were about ideology and international order. But I don’t know that everyone will be surprised that Aron was so interested in biology, so much as they might be unsettled. We associate any contact between political beliefs and evolutionary theory with deeply illiberal commitments, with racism, eugenics, and just plain old bad history. And while it’s true that we should approach attempts to import scientific data into humanist frameworks with caution, we also shouldn’t grant science more explanatory power than it can hold. In recent history, the liberal position has been a vigorous critique of biological determinism, but as Stephen Jay Gould and others repeatedly teach us, the point is not simply that society or history is autonomous from the biological, but that biology itself is not as determinist or totalizing as we sometimes understand it to be. That’s why reading the work of scientists themselves is so important, because it brings out the provisional, ambiguous, and contentious nature of their endeavors. It shows that they aren’t stripping the world of contingency, but rather prodding at and making visible new contingencies.

CR: The history you uncover in your article is incredibly revealing in what it tells us about the intellectual origins of not just Aron’s thought but the milieu out of which many people like him emerged. Do you think there is anything in that history that is of particular relevance or importance for the present?  

IG: Yes, I do think there are really instructive parallels with the present. Aron came of age in a time of enormous political upheaval and two catastrophic world wars. Political and epistemological upheaval go together, and so this generation of French thinkers can speak to our own anxieties about the eclipse of humanities and social sciences by STEM fields. One way to think about this history’s relevance would be to see Aron as a cautionary tale – the science changes quite quickly as the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis takes shape, DNA explodes as a new way to understand life over time, and antihumanism gains cultural strength in France. So it’s not clear that Aron’s study of biology really got him where he wanted to go. But I actually think this picture is a little too cynical, because it ignores what’s so interesting about Aron’s philosophy to begin with. He understood that biology and philosophy were facing some of the same questions, such as how to understand the past from the perspective of the present, and whether laws that explained the present could be known to have operated the same way in the past.

In this way, we ought to pay attention to how STEM fields and the humanities are speaking to some of the same questions. For example there’s been a lot of energy around the concept of the Anthropocene recently, and it’s a perfect opportunity for historians to contribute to a conversation about something that is both a scientific claim—that humans have become a geological agent—and a historical, political, and moral one. We can offer a longer-term understanding of how history and natural history have spoken to one another in the past, how the human has been constructed through philosophy, human sciences, and natural sciences, and how thinking about the end of civilization is saturated with political imagination. Deborah Coen’s work on history of scaling is a great example, as is Nasser Zakariya’s recent book, A Final Story.

CR: I was very interested in what you had to say in your article about bridging the gap between intellectual history and history of science, which is an important issue for an interdisciplinary journal like HHS. The material or practice turn in history of science has been  important  in creating this division, as you explain in your conclusion. This turn needn’t rule out the human, of course, and it hasn’t, as work on subjects like the body shows. But it’s clear, as you explain, that many historians of science see intellectual history as something that needn’t concern them. Why do you think belief is misplaced and what do you think we would all gain by putting the two together again? 

IG: I hope that the story I’ve told in my article illustrates one immediate benefit of overcoming the longstanding division between intellectual history and history of science. Namely, that there is historical work that just hasn’t been done as a result. Aron’s early interest in evolutionary theory, and its effect on his philosophy of history, is not an isolated case. There is enormous potential in fields like the history of knowledge, history of the humanities, as well as in fields like environmental humanities, to bring the tools of intellectual history and history of science to bear on any number of subjects.

But also within intellectual history, the elision of science has meant flawed or at least partial understandings of figures as enormously influential as Aron. At the same time, within the history of science the material turn that you mention led to a kind of reflexive suspicion of philosophy, which John Tresch has written about. Tresch sees the potential of intellectual history in a broader scale for history of science – get beyond the case study. I think this is part of the story, but that on an even more basic level the history of science will be better told if its methodological framework can accommodate the conceptual feedback that exists between science and philosophy, in addition to the feedback between science and society, institutions, and technology. One of the most exciting things about reading the work of French biologists is discovering the degree to which philosophical questions preoccupied them not as extra-scientific or ex post facto interpretations, but as urgent problems to which their research was addressed.

Isabel Gabel is Postdoctoral Fellow at the Committee on Conceptual and Historical Studies of Science at the University of Chicago. Her current book manuscript, Biology and the Historical Imagination: Science and Humanism in Twentieth-Century France, provides a genealogy of the relationship between developments in the fields of evolutionary theory, genetics, and embryology, and the emergence of structuralism and posthumanism in France.

Chris Renwick is Senior Lecturer n Modern History at the University of York, and an editor of History of the Human Sciences. His most recent book is Bread For all (Allen Lane).

Pageantry and the picket line: on the psychology of striking

by Hannah Proctor

Watching the current University and College Union (UCU) picket lines from afar – I’m a postdoctoral fellow based in Germany – I was trying to think if I’d ever come across any psychological writings on striking, and, more specifically on picket lines. Of course, as Chris Millard has pointed out already in this series, strikes are not primarily expressions of feeling; they are withdrawals of labour. Indeed, references to strikers’ ‘deep’ or ‘strong’ feelings in letters by university Vice-Chancellors seem to downplay the material demands being made by striking workers. I was nonetheless interested in finding out whether theorisations of the psychological experience of picket lines – as specific spatial, temporal and interpersonal phenomena – already exist.

Perhaps unsurprisingly a search of the multiple psychoanalytic journals included in the Psychoanalytic Electronic Publishing database for ‘picket line’ yielded just fourteen results.  I looked at the two earliest examples that appeared on this list and in both cases the picket line appeared as a fraught symbol for individual bourgeois analysands. In a discussion of compulsive hand-washing from 1938 a female patient writes a short story whose protagonist is based on her hotel maid’s participation in an elevator operator strike. The patient took up the workers’ cause, organising meetings in support of their actions. In this period of political involvement, the analyst reports, that patient’s hand-washing stopped. As soon as her involvement with the strike ceased (interpreted by the analyst as a form of sublimation), her ‘compulsive’ behaviour resumed.[ref]George S. Goldman, ‘A Case of Compulsive Handwashing’, Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 7 (1938), 96-121.[/ref] In an article from 1943 a ‘frigid hysteric’ patient dreams of a bus trip being cancelled due to a transport strike. In the subsequent interpretation of the dream, which includes a long cutting from a newspaper article on a strike of charwomen the patient had read, the analyst interprets her reaction to the story as relating to her ‘desperately struggling for male status’; she did not ordinarily support strikes on political groundsm but did so in this case due to the gender of the workers.[ref]Edmund Bergler, ‘A Third Function of the ‘Day Residue’ in Dreams’ Psychoanalytic Quarterly, (1943) 12, 353-370.[/ref] In neither example are the patients themselves involved directly in the strikes and neither have first-hand experience of picket lines; the strikes’ psychic significance is tied to existing individual neuroses. Of course, it might be that non-psychoanalytic theories, with less sinister assumptions about group psychology, might be a better place to start for approaching the question at hand. But instead I found myself thinking about the possibility of approaching the question from different fields altogether.

While researching for a recent article reflecting on commemorations of the 1917 October Revolution I found myself reading about early twentieth-century mass spectacles, left-wing pageants and revolutionary dance troupes in the Soviet Union and America.[ref]https://www.radicalphilosophy.com/article/revolutionary-commemoration[/ref] In many of these cases the relationship between ‘actual’ historical events and ‘fictional’ theatrical reenactments proved to be blurry. As the title of a 1933 piece Edith Segal choreographed with the Needle Trades Workers Dance Group in New York indicates – Practice for the Picket Line – workers in union or party affiliated dance groups would create scenarios drawing on their own experiences, which would in turn function as rehearsals for future political action.[ref]Ellen Graff, Stepping Left: Dance and Politics in New York City, 1928–1942 (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1999), p. 43.[/ref] But as a historian of the ‘psy’ disciplines with an interest in affective histories of the left, I was particularly intrigued by how the psychological function of such performances was articulated by their creators, participants and audiences. Perhaps these examples, though remote from the ‘psy’ disciplines, could provide material for thinking through the psychic dimension of the collective experience of picketing.

In January 1913 silk weavers and dyers in Paterson, New Jersey went on strike after four workers were fired for complaining about the introduction of a new four-loom technology that required a less skilled workforce. With the strike still on-going but little coverage of it in the mainstream press, activists and intellectuals in New York collaborated with the striking workers to produce an elaborate pageant in Madison Square Gardens on June 7 1913 , sponsored by the International Workers of the World (IWW). The pageant was intended to publicise the strike and raise money for the strike fund, which was urgently needed as the striking workers and their families were at risk of starvation. But the pageant’s purpose was financial, propagandistic and educational, it was also emotional. The Pageant saw 1,029 strikers reenacting the dramatic events of the picket lines punctuated by familiar songs from the labour movement in which the audience was invited to join.[ref]For the programme of the pageant and other associated primary documents, see:  ‘Paterson Strike Pageant’, The Drama Review: TDR, 15, 3 (1971), 60-71.[/ref] The dramatic, fast-paced temporality of the staged strike differed markedly from the drawn-out nature of the real one but the worker-performers found the rehearsal process gave them a chance to reflect on and process their experiences.  Almost 15,000 people watched the performance which was then described in detail in New York newspapers. The sympathetic leftist publication Solidarity claimed that the performance ‘seized the imagination’, while the hostile New York Times accused it of ‘stimulating mad passion against law and order’[ref]These reviews are cited in Steve Golin, The Fragile Bridge: Paterson Silk Strike, 1913 (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1988), p. 166, p. 169.[/ref]. Although these accounts differed in their political assessment of the production they both emphasised its psychological power. Although the strike was simulated, the passions the reenactment stimulated were real.

The pageant failed to raise significant amounts of money and many subsequently declared it a failure, which distracted workers and took them away from the real pickets outside the mill.[ref]See, Elizabeth Gurley Flynn, ‘The Truth About the Paterson Strike’, Rebel Voices: an IWW Anthology, ed. Joyce Kornbluh (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1965 pp. 214-226.[/ref] Indeed, the organisers produced the spectacle at a loss. The Paterson silk strike itself was soon defeated. Workers began returning to the factory in July and many of their demands were never met. Yet some discussions both by contemporaries and historians insist that the pageant succeeded not only as an aesthetic innovation which inspired future artistic endeavours – John Reed, one of the New York intellectuals who instigated the production would soon leave for Europe; his book Ten Days That Shook the World would become a defining account of the October Revolution inspiring Sergei Eisenstein’s October in turn – but also as a cognitive and affective interpersonal experience which similarly outlived the performance itself. Though sufficient funds were not raised, consciousnesses were  raised (to use the vocabulary of the pageant’s participants and chroniclers).[ref]See, for example, Leslie Fishbein, ‘The Paterson Pageant (1913): The Birth of Docudrama as a Weapon in the Class Struggle’, New York History, 72, 2 (1991), 197-233, Linda Nochlin, ‘The Paterson Strike Pageant of 1913’, Art in America, 62, 1974, 64-68. In her discussion of Segal’s performance Ellen Graff writes that ‘Radicals hoped that mock demonstrations… would prepare workers for actual confrontations as well as engage their sympathies and raise political consciousness.’ Stepping Left, p. 43.[/ref]

The terms ‘class consciousness’ and ‘political consciousness’ in reflections on the performance function as psychological concepts despite rarely having been explicitly understood as such, and as concepts which seem to have gone largely un-thematised within the ‘psy’ disciplines. One starting point for trying to think more about the psychology of the picket line would be to think more carefully about how these terms were used in this context, how they allude to political concepts elaborated by Lenin, Rosa Luxemburg, György Lukács and others, but also depart from or complicate them. I’d be interested in thinking about how an emphasis on gaining a broad intellectual understanding of a political situation was combined with an insistence of the importance of immediate emotional experiences, how emotional experience can allow individuals to situate themselves within a collective, and so on.

Perhaps more central, however, would be a consideration of the function of re-enactment as a form of reflection upon political action (and even as a form of political action in its own right) enabling strikers and their supporters to better understand and communicate their struggle. This might open up ways of approaching the (necessarily very different) forms of reflection, representation and dissemination that attend current disputes. Of course, there is often a kind of theatricality to the picket line as has been evident during the current UCU strikes – which can function to communicate demands, alleviate the tedium of standing around in the cold all day, attract more people to the picket etc – but the example of the pageant brings into focus a slight different set of questions about how striking workers represent and communicate their struggles to themselves and others to forge and sustain the solidarity necessary to resist capitulation. This seems particularly urgent in a context in which collective memories of labour organising can be hard to locate.

The current strikes have not succeeded yet, but UCU branches’ rejection of the deal proposed on Monday (March 12th) indicates that something has shifted during this dispute, which may mark the beginning of a broader resistance to the wider marketization of higher education in the UK. University vice-chancellors’ insistence on invoking the ‘deep’ or ‘strong’ feelings of their striking employees can be read as attempts to reduce picket lines to sites of emotional fracas, or coordinated temper tantrums, strangely divorced from the collective withdrawal of labour. But attending to the psychological dimensions of the picket line could potentially do something very different, offering space for acknowledging the anxiety, frustration, boredom and anger associated with striking, while also allowing us to explore how joyful interpersonal collective experiences can participate in building and sustaining political movements.

Hannah Proctor is a Fellow of the Institute for Cultural Inquiry, Berlin.

Image attribution: The accompanying image, ‘Bus load of children of Paterson, N.J., strikers (silk workers) in May Day parade – New York City] [graphic]’ has been sourced form the online catalogue of the Library of Confress. There are no known restrictions on reproduction. The original can be viewed here: http://www.loc.gov/pictures/resource/cph.3b00599/

On the emotional and material politics of the strike

by Chris Millard

Strikes stir the emotions. The solidarity of picketing, the anxiety of students missing classes, the anger of those who feel wronged enough to withdraw their labour. There are doubtless strong feelings behind the current University and College Union (UCU) industrial action to defend ‘defined benefit’ pensions. These varied feelings have been mobilized in a number of ways over the past few weeks, and this short post (building on some tweets here and here is an attempt to analyse a bit further the emotional politics of striking.

There are a number of distinct parts (both core and peripheral) of the strike action at play at any one time: the picket line, supportive demonstrations and rallies, teach-outs, the implied dissent, and the withdrawal of labour itself. A key aspect of the emotional politics of this strike can be seen in the confusion (both deliberate and unwitting) between a number of these elements.The Vice-Chancellor of The University of Sheffield, Professor Sir Keith Burnett, sent an email to staff where those on strike were characterized as ‘communicat[ing] the strength of their feelings through strike action’ (you can see an extract from that email in this tweet from Sheffield historian, Simon Stevens). This was not a hostile characterization, but it was a serious misunderstanding. It crystallised out some of the issues I’ve had with the strike and on the picket.

As others have pointed out in response to that communication, the point of a strike is not an expression of feeling, it is to disrupt the operations of the employer to force them back to the negotiating table. As Simon Stevens himself put it on Twitter: ‘A strike is an effort to rebalance the material interests shaping the employer’s behaviour by shutting down production and/or operations.’ But this material intervention seems lost, forgotten or at the very least undersold in the current dispute. The idea (often tacit) that ‘so long as you don’t cross the picket, you are not strike-breaking’ is at issue here. If you do work for the university at home, or in a coffee shop, or anywhere else on strike days, you are not striking. If you sit at home on a strike day, and edit an article to submit to the Research Excellence Framework (REF) on a strike day, you are not striking. So far, so orthodox.

The opposite side to this misapprehension is where emotions come in. It is related to the fact that universities increasingly have been seen in recent years as battlegrounds for free speech. The most recent eruptions are over the Prevent agenda and no-platforming; universities have of course for many years been associated with radical protest and demonstrations. These aspects, the expression of dissent, opinion and protest – often couched in terms of articulation of feelings – have become conflated with strike action. Picket lines superficially have many of the material trappings of protests: banners, placards, megaphones and chanting. But their object is quite distinctive from that of a protest. They exist to demarcate a strike area, to put the strike into a spatial idiom. Even if someone is ‘only’ crossing a picket line for ‘one meeting’ they risk signaling that they do not support the strike, regardless of their actual intentions.

We appear to be in a period of flux in how we think about picket lines, and there is real ambiguity about members of other unions, especially if those unions do not support (or are prevented from supporting) the picketing taking place. However, it is perfectly possible to (at least partially) mitigate the crossing of a picket – with stories across universities of people working who brought hot drinks and snacks out to picketers. I am much less sympathetic to people in UCU, often in senior, permanent positions, who choose not to strike because they don’t agree with the particular issue being foregrounded, or the particular tactics employed. If you choose to freelance when asked for collective action, I think you’ve got some hard thinking to do about solidarity. Saying ‘I don’t agree with this or that’ about the action, mistakes a collective agreement to withdraw labour (overwhelmingly voted for by members) for individuals having a protest. By framing the action in this way, protest is foregrounded, and the spatial and material disruption of the strike disappears. Sir Keith met with Sheffield UCU representatives on Tuesday – and was snapped holding an ‘Official Picket’ sign. However, he still committed this error, inviting UCU delegates into his office, which was across the picket line. They refused to cross, but met him later in a neutral venue.

So picket lines are not protests, and they are not about expressions of feelings: they are a spatial manifestation of the collective withdrawal of labour. Strikes are also material interventions that are undermined by all work, even when it doesn’t cross the picket line.” Well, so what? As I see it, this brings into focus the demand to reschedule teaching, which had previously been backed by, by many institutions, by a threat to deduct up to 100% of pay for each day teaching was not rescheduled. (Most institutions have backed down under public pressure on this particular point. A list of institutions not understood to have backed down on this point at the time of writing can be seen here). However, the fact that the demand was made at all is important, in both material and emotional terms. According to the view that mistakes strike action for an expression of feeling, once the feeling is expressed, there is no reason why the teaching can’t be done. It can be rescheduled (the logistical impossibility notwithstanding), because making the point was the point, rather than the withdrawal of labour. In other words: the supportive demonstrations, the protest, the signs, the placards have obscured the core of the strike, i.e. the withdrawal of labour.

But materially this matters too. Pay has already been, or will be, docked for the work not done, so clearly the employers are engaging on this material, financial level. This relation is in turn connected to the financial interests of students: they are paying their fees, so why shouldn’t they get the promised teaching? However, the employers do not follow through on this view of the financial politics of the strike; they do not, for example, propose to repay people for making up the work. They also (as noted) threatened to dock pay again for the refusal to reschedule. This only makes sense if the strike is transformed into a free-floating expression of dissent, of emotion, of feeling. But that logic doesn’t tally with pay-docking.

If the strike is an expression of feeling, then employers should not dock pay on strike days, and the demand to reschedule will become understandable. (The corresponding logic of holding a 14-day demonstration outside places of work is another matter.) On the other hand, if the docking of pay is legitimate as a response to the withdrawal of labour (and the withdrawal is put in spatial terms by a picket line), then the demand to make it that labour is arguably a challenge to the right to strike after the fact. Emotions and feelings matter hugely in this action. But they are not the point of the strike.

Chris Millard is Lecturer in the History of Medicine and Medical Humanities at the University of Sheffield, and book reviews editor of History of the Human Sciences.

This article represents the views of the author only, and is not written on behalf of History of The Human Sciences, its editors, or editorial board.

The featured image, ‘Penn[sylvania] on The Picket Line — 1917’ comes from ‘Women of Protest: Photographs from the Records of the National Woman’s Party,’ Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, D.C. There are no known copyright restrictions with this image. The original can be viewed at this link: https://www.loc.gov/resource/mnwp.160022